Saturday, July 30, 2022

400th Post: An Indulgent Look Back

This will be the fourth post in this series of reflections (link, linklink). Perhaps I "cheated" a bit in these last 100 posts, since roughly two-thirds were publications of newly searchable content on Gordon Clark, several of which are not listed in the bibliography put together by Doug Douma. But I have, at least, felt less burnt out in writing, and I hope that continues as time allows.

As implied by the above, one of my intentions within the past year has been to make headway in a long-standing resolution I've had regarding material pertaining to Gordon Clark. I am attempting to 1) comprehensively chronologize his work (especially public work), 2) make the content of said work searchable online, 3) highlight statements within his thought which have made unique or important contribution to Christian thought, 4) systematize these thoughts, and 5) develop this thought (where necessary). 

That is, the ultimate aim is not simply to restate what Clark believed but rather to use his thought as a foil for a better understanding and defense of God's revealed word. In turn, by God's grace, this will hopefully convict more people of its truth (evangelistic with respect to unbelievers; assurance with respect to believers).

Various blog posts I've already written - even a decade ago now - have been written with this in mind. but my hope is that once I've organized each of these elements (God willing), people will be able to follow my reasoning to my conclusions more easily. 

To this end, I believe I have nearly, if not fully, exhausted what online research is possible that would help fill out the first goal (a chronologized bibliography). I have now transitioned to searching physical locations for copies of periodicals, publications, audio, etc. My recent visit to Emory's theological library enabled me to find and make available a Clark work that had not yet been put online, and I am hoping to check off the same with a visit to ABHS this week (which have physical copies of The Gordon Review). Eventual visits to Covenant College (physical copies of Bible Presbyterian Reporter), Columbia Seminary (The Calvin Forum, Reformed Presbyterian Advocate), and Asbury Seminary (The Home Evangelical), and long term goals of either visiting or corresponding with people who are near to Wheaton College (American Scientific Affiliation) or PCA, WTS, and SDCS archive locations would round out my initial intentions. 

Frankly, this feels mostly like double-checking Douma's work. There are, however, a significant number of items in his bibliography that are not available online (e.g. sermons), and if the content is out there, I would be interested in finding it. Personally, I would also be interested in reading more of Clark's letters, but I also understand sensitivity regarding such materials.

As I've been researching this past year, I've also attempted to engage with more criticisms of Clark. Of course, I've critiqued Clark as much as anyone in attempts to refine his apologetic, but I want to distinguish the right from the wrong. Other, unrelated areas I've posted about have especially involved biblical theology, divine knowledge (especially, in the context of the doctrine of God), and necessitarianism. I have a sincere respect for those who have pushed to deepen our understanding of these areas, and I am always learning just how much more there is to still learn. One truth I come to appreciate more and more is that the prospect of a never-ending life with God does not scare me (as if it could ever be boring or become stale, as I have heard) but rather excites me.

I have more thoughts I hope to post about in the future, such as on original sin, realism, Eastern Orthodoxy, necessitarianism (continued), sacramentology, and epistemology and ontology in general. I did manage to clear out a few posts I've had in draft limbo for a long time now - I only have 10 more at this point (but plenty more ideas for posts and other sources from which to draw content, including weekly sermon notes I've taken for a few years now). I hope to continue to post at the same relative frequency as this past year (not counting the transcriptions of Clark works), but that will largely depend on how my personal life progresses.

And on that note, I will continue to thank God for His blessings and pray for His mercy and grace as I face obstacles - some times of my own making, some times not. As Christians, we ought to trust God's word in Romans 8:28. Let us keep the faith as we continue to run our race.

Monday, July 18, 2022

Puzzling on the Trinity

In a post from last year on Trinitarianism (link), I wrote, "in spite of my above reservations and thoughts, I am not as dogmatic about this as I used to be. The subject is complicated, to say the least! Before all else, I deny that the Father and Son are of different natures." 

Thinking about how monotheism and Trinitarianism are both true can sometimes feel like trying to complete the final piece of a puzzle while blindfolded. It might feel like just one, last piece would complete the puzzle, but there are several pieces within arms reach that could be tested to fit the final, missing space of the puzzle. 

Now, tangibly speaking, a blindfolded person can ascertain that there are certain things that can be known about the missing piece, such as the edges it should have. But suppose several pieces seem to fit the same space. I try one piece, and since it had the wrong edges, I discard it. I another piece, and it seems to fit the puzzle. How exciting! But then I try another, just to be safe... and it also seems to fit!

Perhaps some pieces ended up in the wrong puzzle box. These pieces don't match the picture of my puzzle at all, even if they may seem to fit. Since I am blindfolded, I can't see the puzzle to determine that each piece I try also matches the holistic art of the puzzle itself. But I do know that a puzzle isn't just about fitting in pieces into places. That is, a puzzle is about fitting pieces that should be able to form an intelligible picture which could be recognized if my blindfold was taken off.

Now, I think there must still be a way to determine which piece is correct. Let's imagine this puzzle being multi-layered in that every piece of the puzzle has bumps on it such that if I fit the correct piece into the missing spot, a blindfolded person such as myself could conceivably confirm the piece is correct by reading an intelligible message in Braille. The problem I face now is that I don't know how to read Braille, so I have to learn that first.

Cashing this analogy out, the picture of the puzzle box I am attempting  to construct is the reality, and my epistemic quest is to reconstruct this picture. That is, it may initially seem like there are multiple possible Trinitarian models coherent with biblical revelation. However, this can't be. 

Sure, there may be obvious respects in which models may be similar. And, to a certain point, all puzzlers or believers should have the same pieces or beliefs: the Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct persons; these persons are consubstantial; there is one God. These puzzle pieces are fundamental to the construction of an intelligible puzzle.

But further attempt to harmonize these truths will appeal to a puzzle piece or belief that might have the same edges as the missing spot in the puzzle. Each seems to fit... in a tactile sense. At the moment - and I'll speak for myself - I can't see the whole picture well enough to determine which piece or model is correct. 

I do think, though, there must be a way to determine which model is correct (or if there might even be another similarly edged model I have not yet "grasped"). This is, I admit, just an intuition, perhaps based on that I think I have already grasped several pieces whose edges have seemed to fit the other pieces.

For those who sympathize with this metaphor, "Braille" might refer to any number of things. For my part, I think I need a better understanding of exegetical and metaphysical underpinnings of issues related to Trinitarian discussions. Before I declare a piece is correct, I want more evidence that the Braille message yielded by a given model is intelligible. That means I have to learn more about Braille before I can resolve the puzzle to my satisfaction. 

Another reason I use this illustration, though, is to caution against a rushed interpretation of any script one thinks has formed an intelligible message. Don't get me wrong: the puzzle-piecing process is a good thing. It sharpens our minds and orients us toward good things. In fact, I rather enjoy the puzzle piecing process. That's probably one reason God has set these questions before us as He has - albeit questions which command our caution, attention, and reverence. Conversation we have with other believers helps, as I think it's meant to. 

But we also ought to be faithful in piecing together what parts of the puzzle we can during the time in which we are given - carefully discarding false doctrine as it comes - rather than treating the process as a time-clock scenario in which our salvation depends on our having a completed puzzle. A piece with the wrong bumps is just as false as one with the wrong edges, and the former requires even more care. For while we may be blindfolded in this life, we shall see the truth more clearly in the next. 

The parable of the talents shows how sorry we will be if we are lazy and apathetic towards our Master. This scenario hopefully shows how sorry we will be if we are overzealous.

Thursday, July 14, 2022

Necessitarianism and "Eternal Omniscience"

I still intend to give a fuller treatment of necessitarianism to which I have alluded in a couple other posts (link, link). But after recently finding another piece by Gordon Clark that had not yet been made available online (link), I am prompted to briefly mention two points on the subject:

Firstly, I believe the proposed timeline I constructed as to when Clark changed his mind on the issue of necessitarianism has been strengthened. I wrote:

Given the unqualified disparagement, I take the above to be an argument meant against necessitarianism in general as well as against the Stoics in particular. Then, further, the following was written in 1963, when I gather Clark still rejected necessitarianism...
Now, compare the above to later works in which Clark has - for reasons I again will address elsewhere - revised his view and come to accept necessitarianism. The first two citations are from Clark's books The Trinity (originally published in 1985) and The Atonement (originally published in 1987). Clark had finished both as early as 1977 and had hoped would be published as early as 1978 as parts of a larger book - a systematic theology (link). Some time in this timeframe between 1963 and 1977, it seems Clark's views changed.

For if one reads Clark's reply to Daane (whose thoughts, by the way, I am not intending to defend; while researching material on Clark, I stumbled across what I can only charitably describe as a haphazard, unhelpful "review" that Daane wrote against Clark's book on predestination), Clark appears to deny that divine freedom implies contingent truths. Leaving aside Daane's views in his book, note Clark's own position that he defends in the following quotes from his own 1977 book review of Daane:

Though it may at first be difficult to see what Daane meant by freedom, it soon becomes clear that he does not mean freedom from external control. No doubt God is free from external control, but for Daane this is by no means sufficient for the doctrine of God.

What is worse, or at least what is more obviously unscriptural, Daane argues: "In his freedom God decreed. As an unnecessary decree, as a decree that bears the pedigree of the historical, it might not have been" (p. 77). This means, does it not, that the truth, "Judas betrayed Christ," might never have become true? And though Christ was slain from the foundation of the world, historically Jesus might not have been crucified...

One must face the question, being the kind of God he is, could God have decided against Christ's being crucified before the foundation of the world? Presumably Daane says yes. But then Daane's God is not really the God whom the Bible presents. Omniscience makes Daane's God impossible.

On page 162 we read, "God's creation of the world as his free act is not contrary to rationality, but something other than his rationality requires." On the following page he continues: "Either alternative would accord with his nature." But this statement is something neither Daane nor anyone else can possibly know. Admittedly it seems very plausible to most people that God's nature does not require ten planets in the solar system rather than only six. So far as omnipotence is concerned God could have made this system with any number of planets. But though this is so plausible when omnipotence along is considered, the situation is different when we take omniscience into account. Since there is much that is not revealed in Scripture, our ignorance is such that we cannot know that "either alternative accords with his nature." Therefore, unless Daane can support his premise, there is no reason to accept his conclusion.

Clark intimates that because Christ was [decreed to be] slain from the foundation of the world, the eternal decree itself was or is necessitated (which does not follow). Clark then appeals to God's omniscience several times to support his view, as if Daane is on shaky ground for believing God's eternal decree is not necessitated - by anything external, of course, but also not by anything internal to God

For whatever else Daane may have written, I believe he is well supported by Reformed tradition for implicitly distinguishing between God's necessary/natural knowledge and God's free/decretal knowledge. Read, for example, Richard Muller's Post Reformation Reformed Dogmatics, Vol. III, pg. 412ff. It is Clark who needs to elaborate on why he thinks omniscience precludes divine "free knowledge." He may do so in other place, but he did not do so in this article.

The second point I want to mention in this post is about the very motivation for eternal omniscience on a necessitarian view - or rather, the lack thereof. To do that, I will first quote a recent argument I made against necessitarianism:

Consider what it would mean for God and creation to be ontologically distinct yet for the latter to be necessitated by the former. This would be analogous to a particular understanding of the doctrine of eternal generation - which, even if untrue, highlights the point. If the Father necessarily generates the Son, the Father and Son would be mutually dependent upon one another. Obviously, the Son would depend upon the Father, being necessitated by Him. In turn, however, the Father could be who He is ("Father") without a Son.

So, too, a necessitated creation would mean that the Creator and creature are mutually dependent such that God cannot be who He is ("Creator") without a creation. If necessitarianism is true, then God not only needs to create to be Creator, He needs to be Creator. Creation is no longer contingent, so God as Creator isn't a contingent predicate either. Indeed, it's essential or necessary that He be Creator. There is, then, a real dependence on creation in order for one to be able to refer to God as what He essentially and necessarily must be - Creator.

The point needn't be that the Father-Son relationship is exactly the same as the Creator-creature relationship. One could maintain (as I did and do) that the Father and Son are of the same nature, whereas God and creation are not. In both cases, however, necessitation entails mutual dependency, and this is what changed my mind.

[Side note: on a theistic-contingentarian position, God is still the Creator, but such is not essential to who He is. There is no mutual dependency, guarding divine sufficiency. On theistic-necessitarianism, on the other hand, there is no apparent reason why being "Creator" would be any less integral to the essence of God than any commonly regarded divine attribute. Indeed, perhaps this line of reasoning begins to show that Karofsky's reductive monism does follow from necessitarianism (and, hence, why Christians must disagree with Karofsky).]

In short, for a Christian, theistic-necessitarianism is caught on the horns of a dilemma: 1) a pantheistic concession (such as a theistic-Karofskyan necessitarian would make) would salvage the doctrine of divine sufficiency at the expense of the Creator-creature distinction; 2) on the other hand, a concession that there is a mutual dependency between an ontologically distinct Creator and creation would salvage the doctrine of the Creator-creature distinction at the expense of divine sufficiency.

In bold is one argument I would present against Clark's necessitarianism. Now, further notice that because necessitarianism precludes divine sufficiency, there is less motivation to believe God is eternally omniscient.

What I mean by that is this: one reason I reject libertarian accounts of free will would be that I think such accounts preclude divine sufficiency, for God['s knowledge] would then be contingent on His creation. In fact, this was instrumental to my personal attraction to Reformed theology. To protect divine sufficiency, I would argue God's knowledge must be eternal and not contingent on anything external to His own nature and will (i.e. what I call "eternal omniscience" for shorthand).

But if divine sufficiency is denied (as a necessitarian must do to remain relatively consistent), then that is one less reason to believe eternal omniscience. Clark may argue for eternal omniscience on other bases, but significant portions of his book Predestination would have to be revised, such as:

In contrast with Calvinism the Arminian theory of the will may be called the theory of contingency. Or it may be described as the liberty of indifference: That is to say, no motives determine the will. It can choose the weaker motive over the stronger, or, what is more to the point, it can choose without any motive at all. This ability is frequently called the power of contrary choice. Given a set of antecedents, not only external but also internal, the will’s decision could have been the reverse of what it was. A contingent event is one which may or may not happen. It is devoid of certainty, and therefore cannot be foreknown or predicted. Thus the doctrine of free will is a denial of omniscience. (Predestination, Appendix on "Predestination in the Old Testament")

If necessitarianism allows that God necessarily depends on there being a creation to Himself be [Creator], then God is not divinely sufficient, and Clark's above argument is itself insufficient against Arminianism on this point. And while Clark does, in other parts of the book, certainly supports "eternal omniscience" exegetically, if we stop and think about it, rather than it being the case that the traditional Reformed view on divine free knowledge undermines "eternal omniscience," Clark's view undermines it. 

For if God depends on creation to be [Creator], there can be no a priori reason for supposing it is wrong that God's knowledge also depends on creation. Indeed, it would seem that on necessitarianism, God's knowledge "I am Creator" does depend on creation. Thus, it doesn't appear that theistic necessitarianism can be consistent with eternal omniscience. On theistic necessitarianism, divine eternity and divine sufficiency are undermined.

Tuesday, July 12, 2022

Gordon Clark: James Daane’s The Freedom of God: A Review (Presbyterion)

1977. James Daane’s The Freedom of God: A Review. Presbyterion, 3(1), 37–45.

* Dr. Clark is professor of philosophy, Covenant College, Lookout Mountain, Tennessee. He is also an ordained minister of the Reformed Presbyterian Church, Evangelical Synod.

In his book, The Freedom of God, James Daane sets out to discover the reason for so little preaching on election even in Reformed churches. He wonders "whether the pulpit or the doctrine is at fault" (p. 6). His preliminary conclusion is that (1) Reformed theologians have differed among themselves "profoundly and deeply"; Therefore, they have stopped preaching it for the sake of peace. And (2) as the doctrine was more and more refined, "election became unpreachable."

Since Daane begins and ends his book on the theme of preachability, and since through the middle of the book the same theme frequently reappears, it is wise to consider from the outset what the criteria of preachability are. Are the criteria that Daane uses derive from the Scriptures, or are they his own invention, or does he give any criteria at all? Surely if one is going to distinguish doctrines on the basis of preachability, one ought to know what preachability is.

It is immediately clear, however, in the Introduction that Daane considers Turretin, whom he dislikes throughout the book, to have so refined the doctrine of election as to have made it all encompassing but "as bearing no particular relationship to what Paul designates as God's intent." This is rather suspicious for an introduction.

Since the first chapter is entitled "The Sum and Substance of the Gospel," one may expect a statement that includes the main ideas of election. An author writing on a given subject is not bound to list every element of the gospel, but must he not give a fair account of that part of the gospel he has chosen to discuss through the book? This chapter then is taken as a fairly complete account of what Daane means by election. The subject of Peter's sermon at Pentecost, Daane begins, and the burden of all the mockery as Christ hung on the cross was God's election of Jesus. The Jews at the cross "rejected Jesus' claim to divine election." Repeated references to God's election of Jesus follow, for example, "The resurrection was God's elective act, the act that constituted his election of the man, Jesus of Nazareth.... God made him to be both Lord and Christ. This occurred at the resurrection. The election of Jesus is no abstract, timeless, non-historical truth, which the resurrection simply revealed as an eternal truth heretofore concealed. Jesus had to become God's elect (pp. 10, 11). 

Peculiarities emerge in this first chapter. Doubtless in some sense the Father elected or chose the second Person of the Trinity in the covenant of redemption; this was in eternity and was not historical at all. Yet there seems to be nothing in the Bible that speaks of this as election. The Biblical doctrine of election has to do with God's choice of a certain set of people whom he gave to his Son that he might save them. The resurrection was not God's elective act. Jesus had been chosen to be the Messiah long before the crucifixion or the resurrection; he had been chosen before the foundation of the world. Jesus did not become Lord and Christ at the resurrection. He might have become the Messiah at his birth, but he had always been Lord from eternity. The resurrection did precisely what Daane says it did not do, namely, it declared or made clear that Jesus was indeed the Son of God with power.

By substituting the election of Jesus for the election of certain group of sinners, Daane fails to give the sum and substance of the gospel in "The Sum and Substance of the Gospel."

Presumably Daane thinks that his doctrine of election is preachable but that the doctrine of election as regularly held by the Reformed churches is not preachable. In chapter four, "The Gap Between Election and Preaching," he writes: "Election indeed lends itself to lectures and theological reflection; but it appears impossible to preach - except to those identified as elect by some method that preaching itself does not possess.... The Bible does not teach and the pulpit cannot preach an irreversible judgment as an article of faith" (pp. 19-20).

These assertions are hard to digest. Since it is impossible for any evangelist to identify who are the elect in a large and motley assembly, Daane sets an impossible standard to suit himself. But just why it is impossible to preach election to a motley assembly he does not explain. In fact, if the practice of many evangelists is taken into account, it is plainly false that the pulpit cannot preach an irreversible judgment as an article of faith. This is precisely one of the liberal objection to evangelists who preach hell fire.

On the first page of chapter three, "The Sources of the Gap" between election and preaching, he begins a sentence as follows: "If election is for the elect only, whereas the gospel is to be proclaimed to all men..." (p. 34). Not to repeat the point that the preaching of election is not for the elect only, who are identified before the service begins, it should be further added that the separation between election and the gospel is unbiblical. Election is part of the gospel. Paul preached the whole counsel of God. Admittedly different audiences and different times need one theme more than another. We do not on every occasion preach about the Genesis flood, nor do we for years on end preach on the period of the judges. But eventually a faithful ministry will cover all the Biblical material: flood, judges, and predestination too.

The reader, it is true, will find on the same page the statement that "election belongs to the core of the gospel." But this refers to Daane's own idea of election; it does not mean what the Westminster Confession means. Furthermore, Daane shows his dislike for Berkhof, who is rather close to the Westminster doctrine, and he even calls Hoeksema demonic. Yet he admits that their views on election are the standard Reformed position. But when the creeds say that God has foreordained "whatsoever comes to pass" - a phrase for which he expresses dislike several times in the book - he dismisses the creeds as "scholastic" and even as "medieval scholasticism." Now whether the seventeenth century is to be included in the Middle Ages or not, the doctrine of the Westminster Confession is scriptural. The Scripture says, "[God] has mercy on whom He desires, and He hardens whom He desires" (Rom. 9:18).

There are sections in Daane's book that are hard to criticize, not because it is difficult to find something in them to object to, but because the whole is so completely incredible. For example, Daane rejects predestination because it conflicts with history. He seems to assume that only the end event is predestined and not the historical events leading up to the end. "If every event," he says, "is itself destiny, then nothing moves toward a destiny and nothing comes to pass in the historical sense" (p. 44). Predestination does not mean that each event is by itself the final "destiny." It is predestined, but it is not the end of history. As predestined, it is a part of a series of events that advance toward a climax. Therefore, there is no inconsistency between predestination and events coming to pass in an historical sense. How could anyone be confused on such an obvious point? However, seeing this non-existent contradiction in the standard doctrine, Daane tries to avoid it by introducing the "freedom" of God. What he means by divine freedom becomes somewhat clearer as the book continues; but in the early part of his book he is not explicit, for example, "the truth lies in that the freedom of God by which he decided to go historical" (p. 49).

The alleged antithesis between predestination and history seems to be due to the idea that God's decree is single. Reformed theology, in Daane's opinion, not only asserts that God's decree is one, but it even makes this unity a controlling principle. To support this view of Reformed theology, Daane cites Berkhof and (especially, and at length) Francis Turretin. The difficulty in this view is that, according to Daane, man cannot think of God's decree as simple. By reason of human finitude we always divide the decree into parts, such as the creation, the fall, and so on. This undermines the Reformed system. Daane argues as follows: "Since God is a simple being [according to the Reformed system]... the divine decree must also be a simple, single act. The decretive act therefore is not composed of individual resolves, separable items, distinguishable moments.... When filtered through human reflection, the single decree is fractured into diverse items..." (p. 52).

The confusion is apparent. God's decree is one act, no doubt, but this one act, this single decreeing, includes the complexity of the divine mind. There are of course diverse items, distinguishable from one another: the flood, the call of Abraham, the anointing of David, and so on. In this sense the decree is manifold. Leibniz would have described it as beautiful because it united the greatest degree of unity. Daane's trouble is a confusion of the act, which is one, with the complexity of its contents. Nor is this diversity the regrettable infirmity of human limitations. Daane writes: "If the single decree is such that the distinctions finite minds inevitably make... do in fact characterize it, a number of things follow. First, election and reprobation, although they appear distinguishable to our finite mind, are in reality indistinguishable.... All created reality and history is one single, undefinable, indistinguishable datum..." (p. 53, 54). But whoever held that God cannot distinguish between Abraham and David, between Peter and Judas? Rather do Reformed theologians assert that these differences are established by God himself. Why a single act of decreeing cannot encompass millions of objects Daane nowhere explains.

Chapter five, "History, Eschatology, and God's Repentance," assures the readers that "the gospel was not always true." The reason for this is Daane's dependence on Aristotle. Aristotle held that truth is the assertion of what is. Events that will occur tomorrow are not real. Therefore a statement that it will rain tomorrow cannot possibly be true until tomorrow. Propositions in the future tense become true when the event in question happens. To this argument is may be replied that the statement, "Only by faith can sinners be justified," is an eternal truth. It was true even before Adam fell. And if a general principle, rather than an historical event, does not satisfy the discerning reader, one may consider the proposition, "Christ died." This is surely a dated, historical event. If we place ourselves in Old Testament times, "Christ will die" was true and was true from eternity, because Christ was crucified from the foundation of the world. Hence, contrary to our author, the gospel has always been true. A further logical difficulty with his position is that if a proposition in the future tense is not true, it cannot be used in a syllogism. But we are all content to say, "If it rains tomorrow, I shall stay home." Christians can also say, "If the gospel is preached throughout the world, some will be saved." This inference would be impossible on Daane's view of truth. What is worse, or at least what is more obviously unscriptural, Daane argues: "In his freedom God decreed. As an unnecessary decree, as a decree that bears the pedigree of the historical, it might not have been" (p. 77). This means, does it not, that the truth, "Judas betrayed Christ," might never have become true? And though Christ was slain from the foundation of the world, historically Jesus might not have been crucified. 

In chapter six, "The Election of Israel," Daane offers a substitute for the Biblical doctrine of individual election to salvation. "The first case of election in the Bible," he says, "is God's election of the nation of Israel (p. 99). No verse is quoted, and one naturally thinks of God's choosing Abraham, selecting him out of the other pagans in Ur and sending him on a long journey. Noah was also selected. How is it then that anyone can say that the first case of election is that of the nation of Israel? It is no wonder that "this light from the Old Testament has largely been ignored by all those ecclesiastical traditions which have formed a doctrine of individual election." We shall continue to ignore this light, for this light is darkness. Daane continues, "By approaching election in the first form in which it was historically actualized, we can protect ourselves against an individualistic distortion of election..." (. 100).

But once again, how can anyone think that the first historical actualization of election was the nation of Israel, when Noah lived many centuries earlier? Of course Daane has heard of Abraham: "In choosing Abraham God does not choose a single individual; his election includes the election of his seed." This does not dispose of the cases of Noah and Enoch, nor does it do justice to the case of Abraham. God did indeed choose the single individual Abraham, and he did not choose the others in Ur. Then further, though he chose Abraham's seed, God did not elect Ishmael, but Isaac only. And in the case of Isaac, God chose the individual Jacob and not the individual Esau.

Of course Israel was the chosen nation. As a nation it preserved the worship of Jehovah and prepared for the Messiah. But the election of the nation to play this role is not the individual election of every member to salvation. The national election is subservient to individual election. Salvation is the main concern. Salvation is the most important point in Genesis 15. Even in Genesis twelve, where nation and seed are explicit, there are altars. To suppose that the blessings mentioned in these verses are merely earthly blessings of a posterity and a nation is to misunderstand the whole matter. If such were the case, why should Christians today be at all interested in Abraham? The most important thing is the election of individuals to eternal salvation. One must reject as untenable the statement: "The Bible knows nothing of an individualistic doctrine of election; it knows only of a divine election that involves both the father and son and his seed.... The Bible knows nothing of an individual election with a direct reference to eternity.... As there are no more individuals like Melchizedek, without father and mother, so there is no individual election that is not also social corporate election" (p. 114).

For one thing, the case of Melchizedek itself disprove the general statement that the Bible knows nothing about individual election. Further, Rahab was individually elected. True, she later joined the nation of Israel, and with her household too; but these later events were dependent on her prior personal election. Then what about the many Gentiles whose fathers were not Christians and whose children were not? Of course these elect persons became members of the organized church. But they are members of the organization because they were individually elected. No one denies that Christians have social responsibilities; but the basis it hat first of all they are Christians. Indeed, one is repelled by Daane's slighting reference to "this narrow interest in the individual's salvation" (p. 116; emphasis supplied).

A previous paragraph indicated that Daane speaks of the freedom of God. This theme becomes more prominent in chapters seven and nine. Though it may at first be difficult to see what Daane meant by freedom, it soon becomes clear that he does not mean freedom from external control. No doubt God is free from external control, but for Daane this is by no means sufficient for the doctrine of God. Therefore, one must consider the following passages: "A God who cannot elect without reprobating nations or individuals is not a free and sovereign God" (p. 127). "It is as erroneous to impose inevitable sequences on God's elective action as it is to condition it on man's choice" (pp. 127-29). "Within decretal theology, God's elective ways are so comprehensively searched out and scrutinized that the very necessity of election and grace is seen as grounded in the rational nature of God" (p. 148).

The first of these quotations can be paraphrased by saying, "A God who cannot toss a coin heads without tails being on the under side is not a free and sovereign God." To elect some only, as the Scriptures plainly teach, is ipso facto not to choose certain others. Would freedom allow God to elect some only and also to elect all? This is a freedom to think irrationally. Is God free to create a stone too heavy for him to lift? The question is constructed of a self-contradiction. It is nonsense. Must we defend the sovereignty of God by ascribing nonsense to him? Similarly, the second passage quoted in the preceding paragraph is an assertion that God is irrational. Whatever logical consequences may be deduced from God's elective action are as inevitable as their premises. The Westminster Confession, to which Daane of course does not subscribe, says that "the whole counsel of God... is either expressly set down in Scripture, or by good and necessary consequence may be deduced from Scripture." Thus the Confession rejects Daane's demand that we accept certain premises and simultaneously repudiate the conclusions validly deduced from them. In the present century many religious persons wish to curb their logic by their faith, as Emil Brunner recommends. They define a triangle as a three-sided plan figure and complain that the Pythagorean theorem is inconsistent with the sovereign freedom of God. Like Kierkegaard they make a belief in contradiction the prerequisite of being a Christian.

Possibly Daane might answer that the above ignores the subject of reprobation. Reprobation, however, is but one instance where an author must choose between rationality and irrationality. The principle of logical consistency admits of no exception. He who offends in one points can equally offend in any other. Nevertheless a mention of reprobation is appropriate.

A dozen times Daane quotes the Canons of Dort to the effect that the decree of election and the decree of reprobation are not accomplished "in the same manner." This is a vague phrase and neither Daane nor the Canons of Dort define it. Whatever may be Daane's esoteric sense of the phrase, it is possible, and even likely, that the men of Dort had something in mind that would not satisfy Daane's intentions. For example, they might have meant that election to salvation is based on the merits of Christ and that reprobation is based on the sins of the person reprobated. This satisfies the phrase "non in the same manner," but not Daane's argument. Therefore, it is not true to say that "the rejection of the 'in the same manner' causes decretal theology no end of trouble" (p. 150). Equally untrue is the following assertion: "Election in biblical thought is never a selection, a taking of this and a rejection of that out of multiple realities." And immediately he confounds his readers by mentioning God's election of Abraham rather than some other person in Ur of Chaldees.

Chapter nine, "The Freedom of God and the Logic of Election," is probably the worst in the book. It is chiefly a diatribe against theologians. "Many distinguished theologians rarely sit in the pew, and even less often occupy the pulpit" (p. 152). What is the evidence for this assertion? Does it apply to the theologians of the Westminster of perhaps of Dort? Even if it did, the argument is a non sequitur. Why must Daane assume that the most careful students of Scripture are the least to be trusted? Daane in particular dislikes Turretin. But to say that he and others who hold that God is rational had their roots in Aristotle is forced; it is also ironical because Daane takes his theory of propositions in the future tense directly from that ancient Peripatetic. Nor can one agree that the name Aristotle have to his God was the Absolute (p. 153). Again, "Aristotle's God was not a person," needs qualification. It does not fit in with Metaphysics, Book Lambda. Aristotle in this place asserts that a human being can for short periods of time experience the same type of thought that God always experiences. This seems to presuppose that God is a personal being who thinks.

To return now to matters more immediately theological, Daane in several ways argues that the decretal theologians asserts a simplicity in the divine decree that allows no distinction between creation and the fall, or the fall and Christ's crucifixion. This strain in Daane's thinking was alluded to before. One asks, which decretal theologian holds that creation cannot be distinguished from the crucifixion?

If now one admits that Daane's historical sense is poor but believes that the logic of the situation supports him, we repeat that there is no reason to deny that a single act of decreeing can include several distinct items. But beyond this repetition a rational critic must maintain that God need not be irrational to be free. "Van Til holds that God is exhaustively rational. He is therefore obliged to make God's will an unfree agent of divine rationality" (p. 157). But this is to say that if God is free, he must be irrational. Anything rational is unfree. So also with Turretin: "God's will [in Turretin] is so identified with his essence that the former [God's will] is not free to will anything but that which the latter demands" (p. 159). In other words, Daane demands that God be free from rationality. This means that God must be insane. A few pages further on (164-70) Daane several times speaks of God's going out of himself. But if God goes out of himself, he must be beside himself, as is proper to an irrational mind.

Admittedly, Daane does not want to call God insane. Indeed he says: "God is rational, not irrational. But this is not to say he is exhaustively rational" (p. 161; emphasis his). He had also just said: "Once God is defined as exhaustively rational, no room is left for his will and freedom." But what can this mean but that some parts of God's mind are irrational. Most of God's mind may be rational, but in the recesses of his will reason does not rule. Then as a sort of punch line, he adds: "God's will is no less definitive of God than is his essence." This and similar phrases surely imply that Daane thinks of God's essence as one thing and his will as something else added to it. Such a concept suggests several questions: (1) is God a compound, or is he a simple being? (2) Is it not of the essence of God to have a will? (3) Is divine psychology a faculty psychology? (4) What is the essence the essence of? Could it not be the essence of his will? Or, to repeat early Reformers, God's will is simply God's willing. The difficulties increase. They are exemplified in Daane's statement: "God is free to exist without a decree as well as without a world" (p. 162). This means that God's freedom consists in his having, or his ability to have, a mind without mental content; he is free to exist without ideas, without knowledge, without purpose. Verbally Daane rejects irrationalism. But either he does not see the implications here put forward or he sees them and denies that they are validly drawn. But whether they are validly drawn or whether they are fallacious is precisely the question every reader must settle for himself. To the present writer, the freedom Daane describes seems to be the freedom of a blank mind. And in opposition to Daane, Turretin, his bete noire, was surely correct when he said that the cross must be for "those reprobates who arranged for Christ's crucifixion... the means of damnation."

One must face the question, being the kind of God he is, could God have decided against Christ's being crucified before the foundation of the world? Presumably Daane says yes. But then Daane's God is not really the God whom the Bible presents. Omniscience makes Daane's God impossible.

On page 162 we read, "God's creation of the world as his free act is not contrary to rationality, but something other than his rationality requires." On the following page he continues: "Either alternative would accord with his nature." But this statement is something neither Daane nor anyone else can possibly know. Admittedly it seems very plausible to most people that God's nature does not require ten planets in the solar system rather than only six. So far as omnipotence is concerned God could have made this system with any number of planets. But though this is so plausible when omnipotence along is considered, the situation is different when we take omniscience into account. Since there is much that is not revealed in Scripture, our ignorance is such that we cannot know that "either alternative accords with his nature." Therefore, unless Daane can support his premise, there is no reason to accept his conclusion.

There is even less reason to accept his conclusion in view of the fact that Daane's arguments are frequently fallacious. He says: "When everything is rational, nothing is distinguishable from anything else. In the darkness of rationalism everything is a cow and all cows are black" (p. 163). This is nonsense. Geometry is as rational as anything anyone can think of; but this does not prevent us from distinguishing a circle from a triable. In fact, it is our rationality that enables us to distinguish respectively the theorems describing their diverse characteristics. And surely rationality does not confuse a school boy's mistake with a formally valid deduction.

There is more bad logic. "In decretal theology... whatever happens is ipso facto what God wills. No purpose runs through the stream of events" (p. 169). To be sure, God decrees whatsoever comes to pass - a phrase Daane detests - but how does this exclude purpose in whatsoever comes to pass? God decrees each event for the purpose of exhibiting his own glory; and in subsidiary details God decreed that Abraham should have no ground for boasting. A further purpose of justification is the sanctification that inevitably follows. Naturally the subject matter of geometry is no teleological; but rationality and syllogisms handle teleological subject matter just as easily. Under given conditions, it is rational to choose one line of action and irrational to choose another. Reason dictates the correct choice. Hence there is no ground for saying that decretal theology excludes purpose.

Daane does not and cannot produce one verse which asserts that a particular event was not foreordained. His rejection of the phrase, "whatsoever comes to pass," is an imposition of an alien philosophy on the Scriptures, and the result is a serious distortion. Nor is there a valid point in repeating that predestination in the Bible is in Christ, as if decretal theology had ever excluded the second Person of the Trinity from the divine decreeing. Is it simply not true to say, "Individual election... is regarded [by decretal theology] as an occurrence outside Jesus Christ.... Individual election occurs outside of Christ because God's decree itself does" (p. 179). On the contrary, the Trinity made the decree, all three Persons; and the Trinity decreed that salvation should take place through Christ's sacrifice. Why should anyone insinuate that decretal theologians ever denied this? Note the men he opposes: Turretin, Benjamin Warfield, Abraham Kuyper, Lorraine Boettner, Louis Berkhof. The mention of these excellent theologians shows that the view Daane opposes is the standard view of the Reformed churches. It is also the view of the Bible.

Gordon Clark: Calvinism and Confusion (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1956. Calvinism and Confusion. The Southern Presbyterian Journal, XV (24) 2–3.

An evangelist, several members of a city mission board, and various people in various places have
said to me that faith in Christ must precede regeneration. The evangelist in his sermon told the audience that first they must put their faith in Christ, then they must repent, and then they must be born again.

But this is so confusing. And if the people who hear this type of preaching are not confused, it must be because they do not think about what they hear.

The Bible teaches that man is dead in sin. Before he can do anything spiritual he must be raised from the dead, or, to use another figure of speech, he must be born again. A dead man cannot do anything. Now, since faith is a spiritual activity, pleasing to God, a man must be spiritually alive before he can show the evidences of a spiritual life. That is to say, a sinner must be regenerated and given a new heart before he can believe in Christ. The carnal mind is enmity against God. This Calvinistic message is not confusing. It makes sense and can be understood. But to put the matter in still clearer terms, consider the confusion into which the evangelist throws the doctrine of justification.

Faith is the sole means of justification. This theme was a major part of the Reformation doctrine. Justification by faith was the message that swept away Romish superstition, idolatry and dependence on works. But if faith precedes regeneration, it would be possible for a man to be justified, to be clothed upon with the righteousness of Christ, and therefore to be saved, without being born again. Yet the Scripture very definitely says, Ye must be born again. But of what use would regeneration be, if one is already justified, accepted as guiltless before the throne of God, pronounced righteous - all without being born again? This just does not make sense. It is confusion.

And it is a shame when evangelistic sermons are full of confusion. The message of redemption should be made clear and plain. That is why evangelistic sermons should be strongly Calvinistic.

Monday, July 11, 2022

Gordon Clark: A semi-defense of Francis Schaeffer (Christian Scholar's Review)

1982. A Semi-defense of Francis Schaeffer. Christian Scholars Review. Vol. 11, No. 2. 148-149.

In the Christian Scholar's Review, Vol. X, No. 3 (1981) Dr. Ron Ruegsegger criticizes Francis Schaeffer's philosophy. The article is well researched, well written, and well worth reading. Even so, I find some irrelevancies, one misapprehension, and certain omissions.

The irrelevancies come in the first half of the article. The first half is indeed good, in that it compares Schaeffer's historical and logical remarks with the views of philosophers he opposes. But the method does not seem just. Ruegsegger opposes Schaeffer's interpretation of (for example) Hegel and Kierkegaard on the ground that some recent critics interpret these philosophers differently. The suggestion then is, modestly expressed, that Schaeffer's philosophy suffers therefrom. To argue cogently, however, Ruegsegger would have to show that Schaeffer's interpretation is wrong, and that a recent view is correct. This he does not do.

On page 249 Ruegsegger charges Schaeffer with a logical fallacy. He writes, "Schaeffer frequently defends what he calls the Christian presuppositions against its contradictories, but he seldom argues for it against its contraries." On this point it is the critic who commits the fallacy.

The contradictory of "All dogs have four legs" is "Some dogs do not have four legs." Its contrary is, "No dogs have four legs." Now, being a good Christian presuppositionalist, I wish to defend the true Calvinist position that "All dogs have four legs." To do so, I construct a fine argument in refutation of the thesis "Some dogs do not have four legs." If this latter proposition is false, then the affirmative must be true. But note that if this is what I do, it is not necessary to disprove the contrary also. If the contradictory is false, the contrary must also be false. It is Ruegsegger who falls into the logical blunder with which he charges Schaeffer.

There is another point also. It is similar to the preceding insofar as it charges Schaeffer with missing an alternate view. Schaeffer, when discussing ethics, states that if one abandons Christianity "there are three (and only three) alternatives: hedonism, sociological law, and totalitarianism." The critic insists there are more than three: "utilitarian, intuitionistic, naturalistic, ... and none of these are [sic] reducible to either hedonism, sociological law, or totalitarianism." If the critic will read either Bentham himself, the founder of utilitarianism, or Sidgwick's great work on The Methods of Ethics, he will discover that utilitarianism is based on psychological hedonism, from which is attempts to produce a universal hedonism. 

In connection with Schaeffer's ethics there is another point that his critic objects to. Schaeffer's normative principles are distinctively revelation or biblical; but, complains Ruegsegger, not one of his nine arguments against abortion is biblical. He says "curiously enough" (p. 252), and contrasts Schaeffer's theory with his practice, condemning the latter as "inconsistent." Yet it is not inconsistent," as Ruegsegger almost sees. In opposing secular advocates of abortion and greedy politicians, it is legitimate to use ad hominem arguments. These arguments are legitimate even in geometry. One tries to show inconsistencies in the opponent's position. One tries to point out conclusions, logically drawn from the abortionist's principles but which he either does not like or is afraid to admit in public.

These notes, however, are only a semi-defense of Francis Schaeffer. If I were criticizing him, I should first say that he is not a philosopher at all. To be sure, he discusses certain philosophical problems, but he omits so much that he does not deserve the title. In fact, I rather guess that he admits that he is not a philosopher. His great work lies in other fields, particularly the field of evangelism. And there are others who discuss more of philosophy than he does and still omit a great deal. It is not enough to state that the doctrine of the Trinity solve the one-many problem. One must state what the problem is and show just how the Trinity solves it. It is not enough to assert the trustworthiness of sensory experience in an attempt to avoid skepticism. One must define sensation, prove that there are uninterpreted elements in the mind, show how these can be combined into perceptions, and then develop concepts without assuming, what is factually false, that all men have sensory images. Besides which, one much choose from among Plato's, Aristotle's, and Kant's theories of individuation, or produce a further alternative. Schaeffer is not the only one who omits these essential elements in a philosophy.