Thursday, December 29, 2022

Gordon Clark: Cooperative Evangelism (Christianity Today)

1958. Cooperative Evangelism. Christianity Today. 26 May, p. 18.

Some months ago Christianity published an article in opposition to "separation." Now it publishes another that avoids meeting the criticism that was made of the first one. In defense of having unbelievers sponsor evangelistic endeavors, Mr. Ferm (Apr. 14 issue) quotes Finney as saying, "My duty is to belong to the church, even if the devil should belong to it." Does this mean that it would be a sin to leave a church if the devil controls it? At any rate, Mr. Ferm's argument, during the course of which he asserts, "If it is compromise, then Finney compromised," requires for its validity the unexpressed premise that Finney could not have compromised. Personally I do not hold such an exalted opinion of Finney. Nor do I think that Jesus' preaching in the temple is comparable with being sponsored by unbelievers. Jesus did not have the sponsorship of the Pharisees.

The writer also appeals to Wesley, and rebukes some misinformed person who cited Wesley as a separatist. But now may we ask, is Mr. Ferm a member of the Anglican or Episcopal church? If separation is a sin, then all the Methodists are great sinners, and should return to their parent body. And all the rest of us, with them, should return to the Roman Catholic church. It is instructive to see that articles against separation, that is, against the purity of the Church, are ordinarily quiet as to the Protestant Reformation. Their arguments proceed on the tacit assumption that there are no apostate churches from which obedience to God requires separation. But such synagogues of Satan do indeed exist.

Gordon H. Clark
Indianapolis, Ind.

Gordon Clark: Hymns (Christianity Today)

1958. Hymns. Christianity Today. July 7

The critic snips the sacred page-

His brilliance dims the sun-

He sorts his slips, assigns their age,

And tells who made them one

Indianapolis, Ind.           Gordon H. Clark

Gordon Clark: First Reformed Presbyterian Church of Indianapolis (The Reformed Presbyterian Advocate)

1959. First Reformed Presbyterian Church of Indianapolis. The Reformed Presbyterian Advocate. Vol. 93, No 2, Feb. 15.

The last pastor of the First United Presbyterian Church of Indianapolis died on Easter morning 1957. Since that time Dr. Gordon H. Clark has been filling the pulpit. During that year the United Presbyterian Church in the U.S.A voted to merge. But the First church of Indianapolis, because of the widespread unbelief in the U.S.A church, unanimously voted not to enter the merger. It also voted unanimously to seek admission to the Reformed Presbyterian Church, General Synod.

When this request was received by Western Presbytery, the Presbytery appointed a committee to visit the congregation. After the visit the Presbytery at its meeting of Nov. 5, 1958 voted to receive the congregation. The people of Indianapolis greatly appreciate this action. It was not altogether easy action to take. The new United Presbyterian Church will probably lay claim to the Indianapolis property. They have nearly always done so before, and they are pressing a case against a congregation in the state of Washington, which like the Indianapolis congregation, cannot conscientiously merge with unbelief.

The Indianapolis people entertain hopes that the new United Presbyterian church will not press such claims; they also hope that if such claims are pressed, certain local legal conditions will enable them to retain the property. But as the cannot know the future with certainty, the Western Presbytery ran the risk of some slight embarrassment. It could be that the congregation will lose its building and disintegrate.

In the meantime the work is not discouraging. Although there is no regular pastor, the attendance continues at a good level. This winter it has been exceptionally good. The Sabbath School is taxing the resources of the congregation. There are not enough teachers for the children.

At the present time, the Rev. and Mrs. Alvin Sneller, who are missionary appointees to Japan of the Foreign Board of the Reformed Presbyterian Church, are conducting a visitation campaign of the membership and of the neighborhood. The Snellers have a period of five to six weeks before they sail in which to do this work. The results are gratifying. And while the congregation will be sorry to see them go, the quality of their work argues well for their efforts in Japan. The congregation must now make further arrangements during this time of transition.

Gordon Clark: The Resurrection (The Reformed Presbyterian Advocate)

1959. The Resurrection. The Reformed Presbyterian Advocate. Vol. 93, No 3, Mar. 15.

The preaching of Christ's resurrection from the dead is not always attended with success, if success be measured by the number of converts. When Paul preached to the Stoics and Epicureans, they were willing to give him polite and curious attention so long as he discussed the merits of monotheism in opposition to idolatry. The idea of a universal God, in whom we live and move and have our being, interested and even appealed to them. But when Paul began to tell them about Christ's rising from the dead, some mocked, and others said, we will listen to you later, perhaps.

Since the days of Paul philosophers have frequently had difficulty with the resurrection and with other particular historic events of the Christian gospel. Not very many preachers enjoy the opportunity of preaching to philosophers. Paul did not often preach to them, mainly because they form such a small proportion of the population. But highly educated persons, though few in number, have a wide influence. Even if they are relatively unknown during their life time, their ideas become the accepted principles of a later generation. They teach their students, who soon become the teachers of larger numbers; their ideas permeate the school system, and so it happens that philosophers come to control the thinking of a nation.

In the seventeenth century the philosopher Spinoza published an attack on the Bible and propounded a mechanistic philosophy. A century later his ideas had became very popular, at least in Germany. Today his influence has waned, yet one of his criticisms of Christianity is still widely accepted. The characteristics of Spinoza's philosophy were such that he could not admit that religion has anything to do with particular events of history, such as the resurrection. Religion in his opinion consists entirely of abstract, universal truths. He might have been willing to say that God is love, but not that God called Abraham individually, or that the death of Christ has any religious significance. For Spinoza history and religion cannot mix. 

In the nineteenth century Soren Kierkegaard, a Danish philosopher and theologian, though he differed from Spinoza in many ways, also taught that all temporal, local, historical elements should be removed from religion. God is eternal and cannot act in time. The life of Christ, his birth, death, and resurrection took place in time and as such cannot give us the presence of God.

Later disciples of Kierkegaard give this theme a modern twist. These men were disturbed by the results of the higher critical approach to the Bible. Destructive criticism had denied the accuracy of much of the Old Testament, and have even failed to produce a reliable account of the life of Jesus. The trouble was not that these men, now usually called neo-orthodox, were reluctant to abandon the trustworthiness of the Bible. Indeed, they had no desire to defend the Virgin Birth, the details of Christ's ministry, or his divine claims, and still less desire to defend the Old Testament. What bothered them was the idea of a religion that has to change its principle with every new critical theory. The critics at one time pictured Jesus as a good ethical teacher, and such a view satisfied Renan and the modernists.

But after a time it proved insipid. Then other critics said that Jesus started out as an ethical teacher, but that later in his life he came to believe that he was the Messiah. Or, again, that he often talked in terms of Messiahship, but he did not really mean it; it was only a pedagogical device to put his message across the the Jews in terms they could understand. So the theories came and went. But how could any satisfactory religion be based on the ever changing result of historical criticism. The thing to do therefore is to divorce religion from history. In this way the Bible can be completely false; it makes no difference what theory of history one holds; and still "Christianity" remains untouched - so they thought. Indeed, so they still think.

Yet there are some paragraphs of history too well attested to be comfortably denied. No one dare deny that the Christian movement began in the first century. No one dare deny that it suffered persecution first at the hands of the Jews and then at the hands of the Romans. Then too no one dare deny that the early Christians and particularly their leaders were Jews and on the whole were ordinary men. What is it then that explains the power these fishermen exerted against the political organizations of the day. Where did they get their message and what gave them their courage?

The critics conclude that something must have happened. In tones of false piety they solemnly say that something very unusual must have happened. Only, of course, we have no idea of what is could have been.

There is good reason why unbelievers today hesitate to say exactly what happened. In the past several attempts had been made. Some said that the body of Jesus was stolen from the tomb by the disciples. Others said that the disciples experienced an hallucination. But all these attempts, upon analysis, have failed to explain the rise of Christianity. Hallucinations do not explain the empty tomb, and Roman soldiers would not have allowed the disciples to steal the body. Today therefore the unbeliever critics have adopted the wiser policy of saying that something must have happened, but that we have no idea what it was. In this way history will not disturb their religion.

History, however, should disturb their religion. Like the Stoics and Epicureans they may brush aside historical guestions; but unlike the ancient philosophers men of our day have two thousand years of Christianity to explain. There has been a continuous observance of the death of Christ in the Lord's Supper, and an equally continuous observance of the resurrection, not merely once a year at Easter, but more importantly on the first day of every week. These observances go straight back to the disciples themselves. Certainly something must have happened.

And we know very well what it was. The historic documents, i.e. the New Testament books, make it very plain and unambiguous. Jesus died on the cross. His body was laid in the tomb. On the first day of the week he became alive again, walked out of the tomb, and continued to teach his disciples for forty days. 

If Christ be not raised, our faith is vain. But now is Christ risen from the dead. The strife is o'er, the battle done; the victory of life is won; the son of triumph has begun. Alleluia!

Wednesday, December 28, 2022

Gordon Clark: Nothing to Fear (Christianity Today)

1957. Nothing to Fear. Christianity Today. Mar. 18, Vol. I, No. 12.

Professor Handspicker holds that I missed the point in my reply to Mr. Yeaman and insists that I should either prove the historical existence of the Hittites or keep quiet about the fact that orthodoxy has always accepted them as historical.

First, I disclaim any such obligation in a short reply to Mr. Yeaman. It seems to me legitimate to assume that the historicity of the Hittites is commonly acknowledged today. The evidence, on display in the Oriental Institute, cannot be put in this column.

Second, Mr. Yeaman assumed that a certain discovery settled the unimportance of the Virgin Birth; and his argument presupposes that the acceptance of discoveries is an intellectual obligation. I put the word discoveries in quotation marks to suggest that the alleged discoveries of scholars (in the past hundred years) often have been false conclusions. Professor Handspicker takes my quotation marks as evidence of shut eyes and a closed mind. On the contrary I have with open eyes seen clearly these nineteenth century blunders.

Third, when Professor Handspicker asserts that both Mr. Yeaman and I, at a certain point, express our theological commitment and not our scholarship, he makes a disjunction which, though common, is in my opinion faulty. The conclusions of scholarship are invariably related to the scholar's theology. This is the reason, I believe, why the existence of the Hittites was denied.

Now, finally, if my faith were based on the changing opinions of scholars, then indeed it would have a shaky foundation. Since Professor Handspicker does not tell us what foundation he would identify as a rock, it would be inappropriate to embark on further speculation here, for I judge that he and I would not agree as to what the criterion of truth is. But can anyone doubt that the orthodox acceptance of the Hittites was correct and that the scholarly discoveries were false? Gordon H. Clark
Butler University
Indianapolis, Ind.

Gordon Clark: Magazine Religion (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1955. Magazine Religion. The Southern Presbyterian Journal. Sep. 21. 5.

Magazine Religion

By Gordon H. Clark. Ph.D.

In the past little while religion has become a topic for the popular magazines. No doubt the insecurity of the post-war situation has revealed the superficiality of modernistic optimism and the hopelessness of out and out naturalism. To avoid an emotional burden that leads to insanity numbers of men and women are turning their thoughts to religion. And the magazines recognize the interest value.

What kind of religion do the magazines offer? This is a question of some importance. A part of the answer is to be found in an article entitled, Can a Scientist Believe in God?" by Warren Weaver of the Rockefeller Foundation. This article first was published in Look, and it seemed so excellent to the editors of the Readers Digest that they not only republished it but are trying to circulate reprints of it.

For Dr. Weaver the fact that we cannot see God is no more of a reason for not believing in God than the fact that we cannot see electrons is a reason for not believing in electrons. Electron is a name for a set of phenomena that happen with regularity. No one can deny that these phenomena occur, and electron is their name. Therefore electrons exist. Similarly, argues Dr. Weaver, God is a name for another set of consistent phenomena. No one can deny that men, when they are deeply troubled, find comfort in hymns and memories of childhood; no one can deny that in moral crises men sometimes feel a sense of guidance, a hunch, a conviction that such and such is the right thing to do. Other similar experiences are also undeniable. Well, then, God is the name for these phenomena just as electron is the name of other phenomena. Therefore, concludes the article, a scientist can believe in God.

We wish to ask, however, whether a scientist who gives a name to certain phenomena actually believes in God or not. Does the word God mean for the Christian a set of emotional experiences? Or is God a living personal Creator? An atheist can believe that these sets of phenomena occur; he would not deny their reality. But an atheist is honest enough not to call these experiences God. They are simply our experiences. Between the atheist who uses language and the person who tries to sound religious by a tricky use of names, there is some advantage on the side of the atheist.

The important question is not so much. Does God exist? but. What is God? This question may sound like dry-as-dust theology, but the issues of theology go to the center of our very being. What is God? is a very important question. And Presbyterians who have been brought up as Presbyterians know the answer from childhood. Do you remember your catechism? It does not say, God is a name; it says, God is a... (Can you finish it?)

Gordon Clark: Review of Antinomianism in English History by Gertrude Huehns (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1953. Review of Antinomianism in English History by Gertrude Huehns, The Southern Presbyterian Journal 15 Apr.: 17.

Antinomianism In English History

By Gertrude Huehns. The Cresset Press, London, 1951. Pages 200.

There were several groups of Antinomians in the middle of the seventeenth century, all of which the author classifies under Puritanism. Their impact on politics before, during, and after Cromwell, with a concluding chapter on New England, forms the author's field of investigation.

Because of her interest in history the author wishes to show that Antinomianism has a wider appeal independent of its precise doctrinal meaning; but it is the lack of doctrinal preciseness that seems to detract considerably from the value of the book. For example, an antinomian attitude "appears to us to consist mainly in an assertion of the significance of human behavior irrespective of ulterior rational or utilitarian considerations" (p. 5). This basic principle of interpretation, nowhere definitely defended in the book, is somewhat ambiguous.

If rational and utilitarian values include spiritual blessings and eternal rewards, then the sentence does not fit the Antinomians; if eternal values are not included, then the principle would apply as well to other Puritans.

The dependability of the book is further put in doubt by a sentence such as this: "Thus Antinomianism combined (certain ideas) with the Arminians' belief that assurance as to one's place in the final scheme of things may well be gained here on earth" (p. 47). Does the author confuse Arminianism with Calvinism? And again, "The notion of the royalty of Christ is also originally a Baptist one" (p. 128). This is hardly true whether royalty means the kingship of Christ or more narrowly a millenial reign. The reader therefore is left dissatisfied on many pages, and perhaps the chief value of the book is to call attention to a field that might well be worth a serious and- extended study. Our memories of Puritanism have grown too dim.

— Gordon H. Clark.

 

Gordon Clark: Personal Notes on Buswell’s review of A Christian View of Men and Things

The following are notes Clark wrote in the margins of Buswell's critical review of Clark's book, A Christian View of Men and Things. I've written Clark's notes below (leaving out spelling and other editorial corrections he made of Buswell's review. In [brackets], I outline what Buswell wrote that I think the note by Clark is meant to correspond. Notes are separated by --------------------, and any underlining (used for emphasis) are Clark's own. One can read the original notes here to check whether my interpretation in brackets make sense.

These notes appear to be a precursor to a published review Buswell wrote on Clark's book here. To this publication, Clark published his own reply here, which generally follow the notes below. They also contain slightly additional content to Clark's published reply. 

c.1952. Personal Notes on Buswell’s review of A Christian View of Men and Things

Not the point [Clark’s reply to Buswell that “Christian doctrine that God has ordained that governments shall rule and that they shall be instituted through human instrumentality” (emphasis Clark)]

Granted kings may be a human creation, but do [these]? human creators give their creations just powers [Clark has an arrow pointing to this note from his other note that Buswell’s above statement is “Not the point”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Do the angels use coercion? [Clark’s reply to Buswell’s statement that “Now certainly coercion is analytically a part of the idea of fatherhood as the word is used in the Scriptures. Moreover, among the angels who know no sin we have indications of authority, government, and relationships involving superiority, subordination, and presumably coercion. The words “angels and archangels” are not meaningless.”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Kindly cite your evidence [Clark’s reply to Buswell’s statement that “Clark is quite wrong in saying the context that the idea these proofs are not logically or mathematically demonstrative is “contrary to the Catholic” position.” I think that Buswell is saying that “Thomas Aquinas and the Roman Catholics” believe, like the Protestants Clark alludes to in A Christian View of Men and Things, “that traditional arguments from nature to the existence of God are not logically or mathematically demonstrative.” Clark wants evidence for Buswell's assessment about Aquinas and/or Catholics.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

? Hodge said precisely what I said.

Calvin has no demonstrative proofs. [Both of these statements by Clark are in reply to pushback Buswell offers against Clark’s original statement in A Christian View of Men and Things that “Protestant theologians… usually repudiate natural theology”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

This is not the cosmological argument [Clark’s reply to Buswell’s suggestion that a citation he makes of Calvin contains a cosmological argument]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

How know the Law comes from God [Clark’s response to Buswell’s evidentialist argument that “Isaiah clearly required that circumstantial evidence, namely, conformity to the Law and Testimony, should be used by the people to discriminate between the voice of God and the voice of a false prophet.”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Irrelevant [Clark's response next to a paragraph in which Buswell affirms first principles and basic presuppositions but “repudiates the assumption that these foundations may not be questioned or re-examined or substantiated and reinforced.”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

? [Written next to a statement by Buswell that Clark has not provided constructive support or any great system of Christian doctrine.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

What truth is this! [Clark's reply to Buswell's introduction of the idea of a “truth not yet so embodied [in propositions].”

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

This is not nonprop. [Clark's reply to an attempt by Buswell to give an example of a non-propositional truth. Buswell actually gives an example of a proposition and seemingly conflates "propositions" with what might be called "discoveries" (e.g. propositions which men do not yet known because their truth-value has not yet been discovered).]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Quite so. And God is eternal mind. [Clark writes this in reference to a paragraph by Buswell summarizing Clark’s argument that "Without a mind, truth would not exist."]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

? [Clark writes this note next to Buswell's statement that "truth, in ordinary usage, may not be formulated in proposition."]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Why not? [Asked in response to Buswell’s claim that the fact “God has always known all truth does not in the least imply that being known to a mind is of the essential character of the truth as such.”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

i.e. as a premise

quite so [both replies to Clark’s own argument that "if God is known through nature this would make God dependent upon nature." Clark equates "through" with "as a premise" and further accepts Buswell’s analogy that Clark must think that if we know God through truth, then God is dependent upon truth.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

2 thoughts may but need not be the same. [Clark's reply to a misunderstanding by Buswell, who suggests a thought about Mr. Shasta today is not evidently the same as his thought about it yesterday.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Isn’t God a Spirit? [Clark’s reply to Buswell taking exception to Clark’s saying “God’s mind is God” simpliciter.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Quite so [Clark's reply to Buswell's question, “Does [a wicked man or Satan himself] have "a vision of God" or have "contact with God's mind"?" just because these wicked individuals may know any truth.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Not so

No [Buswell thinks Clark attempts to prove God exists by the existence of truth and compares this to the cosmological argument. Clark denies that he attempts to do this.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Where is the observational proof? [Clark’s reply to Buswell's attempt to point out an inconsistency between a statement by Clark that “science… is incapable of arriving at any truth” by comparison to another statement "by Clark" in a following paragraph about “a philosopher [who]... stated the exact truth...”]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

? [Written by Clark next to a statement by Buswell about what Clark would have done if he really were - according to Buswell - using the word “truth” in a consistent manner across various pages in A Christian View of Men and Things.]

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

No [Clark refuses Buswell’s identification of Clark’s position with A. J. Carlson, the latter of whom Clark quotes as divorcing faith or belief from knowledge.]

Tuesday, December 27, 2022

Gordon Clark: Unnamed Letter to the Editor 2 (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1951. Unnamed Letter to Editor. The Southern Presbyterian Journal Vol. X, No. 1. Nov. 28

Sir:

In the issue of Oct. 31, an open letter from an unnamed correspondent states, "You appear to think Christianity to consist in the acceptance as true of certain facts... Saving faith is not the acceptance of facts, historical or theological."

By an interesting coincidence I then turned to study the Sunday School lesson for Nov. IL In the Adult Uniform Lessons Dr. Holmes Ralston writes on p. 60, "When God gives the Ten Commandments to Israel, they are prefaced with the statement: I am the Lord thy God, which have brought thee out of the land of Egypt, out of the house of bondage. If you will take a concordance and follow this expression through the Bible, you will find that it occurs constantly as a revelation from God."

Thank God that he reveals himself, not only in words, but also in facts, redemptive facts. "What God does the unnamed correspondent worship, if not the God who foreordained and executed the facts of the Bible?

Gordon H. Clark, Ph.D.

Butler University

Indianapolis, Ind.

 

Gordon Clark Review of The Philosophies of F.R. Tennant and John Dewey by J. Oliver Buswell (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1951. Review of The Philosophies of F.R. Tennant and John Dewey by J. Oliver Buswell. Southern Presbyterian Journal. 14 Feb.: 14.

THE PHILOSOPHIES OF F. R. TENNANT AND JOHN DEWEY. by J. Oliver Buswell. Jr. Philosophical Library. $6.

Dr. Buswell, President of Shelton College, undertakes in 500 pages to show that the particular applications of empirical method by two philosophers prevent them from arriving at the Christian position. In this he is eminently successful. He also argues that the empirical method, if properly enlarged, would serve as a basis for Christian apologetics.

The work is of course intricate and detailed. Perhaps this necessary virtue is its chief fault. So many points are raised and so many incidental criticisms are made in the extended analysis that a unified impression is difficult to obtain. Sometimes a footnote steals the show; for example note 48 on pp. 309-313 is particular interesting and intrinsically important.

Of course, in a work like this, there are always questions of historical interpretation. For example, Dr. Buswell objects to Dewey's statement that "Descartes defined natural existence as extension" (pp. 365-366) ; and Dr. Buswell gives some reasons for his objection. None the less, Dewey's interpretation is the usual one. See Windelband, History of Philosophy (tr. by Tufts) pp. 405-406; and B. A. G. Fuller, History of Philosophy (1945) Part II, p. 65.

Or again. Dr. Buswell asserts (p. 181), "The fact that Descartes advanced an inductive form of the ontological argument is known to very few. Philosophy teachers of my acquaintance are inclined to deny it." And later (p. 185) "Descartes labels the argument an a posteriori one in so many words. It is truly amazing that the fact has not been more widely recognized.

There is really nothing amazing at all. Most philosophers agree that Descartes gave two proofs of God's existence, though some subdivided them and count the four. No one denies that the first of the two is an a posteriori. The point at issue is whether a posteriori argument, an inductive argument, one that proceeds from effect to cause, can properly be called ontological, as Dr. Buswell calls it. An inductive ontological argument, in my opinion at least, would be an a posteriori a prior argument; and I would conclude that neither Descartes nor anyone else ever produced such a monstrosity.

Dr. Buswell is to be commended for making a courageous attack on unbelief in the field of scholarship. May this book of his stimulate others to make a similar attempt. — Gordon H. Clark.

Gordon Clark: Studies in the Doctrines of The Complaint

Winter 1946/1947. Studies in the Doctrines of the Complaint (PCA Archives and SDCS)

STUDIES IN THE DOCTRINES OF "THE COMPLAINT"

Serious doctrinal issues have been raised in The Orthodox Presbyterian Church during the years 1944-1946. The thirteenth General Assembly elected five ministers to study these doctrines so as to protect the Church from error. It is the conviction of many of the ministers that the Doctrines of The Complaint are not the doctrines of the Word of God or of our subordinate standards. We believe that in several respects The Complaint goes beyond the Confession and is contrary to the historic position of the Reformed Churches. This paper is one of several which, appearing during the winter of 1946-1947, aim to preserve the original position of The Orthodox Presbyterian Church.

Gordon H. Clark

THE PHILOSOPHY OF “THE COMPLAINT.”

At the General Assembly of May 1946, following a speech by Dr. Van Til, I began a defense of my position. As it took fifty minutes to complete the introduction, wisdom dictated that the Assembly take a recess. The remaining days of the Assembly seemed to me to offer no compelling moment for the main part of my speech. And therefore I take this opportunity to present some of the main material. As an introduction to this paper I should like to indicate my own position on the incomprehensibility of God, and then by way of contrast discuss the theory of the Complaint.

It may be remembered that at the General Assembly I expressed my whole hearted approval of that early portion of Dr. Van Til’s address, in which he summarized the doctrine of the incomprehensibility of God. With his explicit remarks in that part of the speech, I agree.

Furthermore, with some of the material in the Complaint contains several columns of quotations from standard reformed writers. These writers are important representatives of Calvinism, and yet they are not infallible. Since, too, the quotations were selected to fit the tenor of the Complaint, it may be that these quotations contain unguarded statements. At least, the quotations may possibly be so made as to alter the intention of the authors.

For example, in The Complaint, page 3, column 2, Charnock is quoted as saying, “it is utterly impossible either to behold him or comprehend him.” As quoted in the Complaint, this may give a wrong impression. Charnock in the context is talking about literal vision with the physical eyes. In this sense it is, as he says, impossible to “behold” a pure Spirit. But the doctrine of the Complaint, as will be shown, implies that it is utterly impossible to contemplate or behold God with the mind. This is not the force of Charnock’s paragraph; and it is not true. The complainants, by omitting the information that Charnock is speaking of physical sensation, attempt to make it appear that Charnock supports their own, very different, position.

However, if these quotations be detached from the Complaint, the following sentences in particular state nothing else than the truth, as I see it. With these statements I fully agree.

“We cannot have an adequate or suitable conception of God” (Charnock).

“It is utterly impossible to have a notion of God commensurate to the immensity and spirituality of his being” (Charnock).

When it is said that God can be known, it is not meant that he can be comprehended. To comprehend is to have a complete and exhaustive knowledge of an object. It is to understand its nature and relations… God is past finding out. We cannot understand the Almighty to perfection” (Charles Hodge).

In this excellent statement by Charles Hodge, attention should particularly be drawn to his definition of comprehend. It seems that neither side in the present controversy has always used the term in this exact meaning. Clarity would be more perfectly attained if all of us could limit ourselves to this one meaning. But the force of English usage had led us to think of incomprehensibility as meaning unintelligibility. And it seems to me that the Complaint teachers rather the unintelligibility or the irrationality of God than the incomprehensibility of God in Hodge’s sense of the term.

The Answer, which still deserves more thorough study by all those interested in the present matter, was written with the Complaint sharply in view. In opposition to the Complaint’s view that incomprehensibility means irrationality or unknowability, the Answer defends the view of Charles Hodge that “to comprehend is to have a complete and exhaustive knowledge.” This meaning does not require the conclusion that God cannot be known at all. It means rather that we cannot know all about God. Therefore, in its account of the doctrine, the Answer put in the very first place an assertion that incomprehensibility must not be so understood as to deny that God can reveal truth. With this foremost assertion of the possibility of revelation the Answer gives a fair, even if not as “adequate” account of the doctrine. Since I am one of its authors, it obviously represents my views.

The Answer, page 9, says, “Dr. Clark contends that the doctrine of the incomprehensibility of God as set forth in Scripture and in the Confession of Faith includes the following points: 1. The essence of God’s being is incomprehensible to man except as God reveals truths concerning his own nature; 2 The manner of God’s knowing, an eternal intuition, is impossible for man; 3. Man can never know exhaustively and completely God’s knowledge of any truth in all its relationships and implications; because every truth has an infinite number of relationships and implications, these must ever, even in heaven, remain inexhaustible for man. 4. But, Dr. Clark maintains, the doctrine of the incomprehensibility of God does not mean that a proposition, e.g. two times two are four, has one meaning for man and a qualitatively different meaning for God, or that some truth is conceptual and other truth is non-conceptual in nature.”

But while these several quotations all reflect sound doctrine, this sound doctrine may be, and in the case of the Complaint part of it has been embedded in a document which by its philosophy and epistemology deviates from the sound doctrine it quotes. Sometimes, as in the case of Dr. Van Til’s address in General Assembly, the complainants summarize the doctrine quite acceptably; but when they develop their views, as they have in the Complaint, it is seen that their epistemology so distorts the doctrine that the resultant whole cannot logically be regarded as reformed. The source of the difficulty and the chief issue between the two parties is epistemological. The men who wrote the Answer maintain the position of Warfield, Hodge, Charnock, and Calvin. That the Complaint does not consistently hold this position, but that it alters and vitiates the doctrine by an untenable epistemology, it is the aim of this paper to prove. 

To this end the paper discusses first, the Philosophic Background of the Complaint; second the The Philosophy of the Complaint; third, A Subsequent Paper; and fourth, The Biblical Doctrine.

THE PHILOSOPHIC BACKGROUND  

The necessity of examining the philosophic background of the Complaint is seen in the fact that certain members of the Assembly openly admitted that they did not understand the issues and accordingly based their votes on their confidence in the ability and scholarship of the complainants. Now, it is not unreasonable for people to follow their trusted leaders when they cannot judge the merits of a case for themselves. But there comes a time to examine the basis of such confidence. A perpetual and blind following of any human leader is not the mark of an educated and conscientious person. The Rev. Robert H. Graham, in a letter dated July 8 1946, speaks of the authors of the Complaint as theological giants. That is his privilege. It is the privilege of all to examine the evidence to see if his estimate is supported by a study of their writings.

Dr. Van Til’s views are obviously the philosophic background of the Complaint. Therefore to understand the Complaint, one must examine the philosophy of Dr. Van Til. Now, his views were formed partly by his study of the history of philosophy; and it is also true that his interpretations of history of philosophy is colored by his views. Inasmuch as he has written at length on this history, let us first examine his work in this easily tested field. 

To show how Dr. Van Til expounds the views of other men, let us first turn to his Syllabus on Apologetics, page 84, where he is discussing medieval philosophy. He says, “In stating the problem (whether universals are ante rem, in re, or post rem) the scholastics fails to distinguish between God and man. They did not ask first whether the ideas of universals were prior to a thing known in the case of God, in order then in a separate question to ask whether the universals were prior to a thing in the case of man.” Now contrast Dr. Van Til’s understanding of medieval philosophy with that of Windelband, History of Philosophy and, History of Philosophy, page 299: “Even Abelard, however, explains this likeness of character in a multiplicity of individuals upon the hypothesis that God created the world according to archetypes which he carried in his mind. Thus according to his view, the universals existed firstly, before the things, as conceptus mentis in God; secondly, in the things, as likenesses of the essential characteristics of individuals; thirdly, after the things, in the human understanding as its concepts and predicates acquired by comparative thought (italics, Windelband’s)... As regards the real question at issue he had advanced so far that it was essentially his theory that became the ruling doctrine in the formula accepted by the Arabian philosophers – Avicenna – ‘universalia ante multiplicitatem, in multiplicitate, et post mutiplicitatem;’ to universals belongs equally a significance ante rem as regards the divine mind, in rea as regards Nature, and post rem as regards human knowledge. And since Thomas and Duns Scotus in the main agreed with this view, the problem of universals, which, to be sure, has not yet been solved, came to a preliminary rest, to come again into the foreground when Nominalism was revived.” 

It is clear that Dr. Van Til says that the scholastics did not do what as a matter of well known fact they did do. It should be specifically noted that this is not just a question of interpretation. Someone might want to defend Dr. Van Til on the ground that every philosopher proposes his own interpretations of the previous philosophers. One man has one view of the scholastics and another man has a different view, and Dr. Van Til is entitled to his. This is not the case at issue. The point is that Dr. Van Til has not correctly represented the views in question. He has said that the scholastics failed to do what as a matter of plain historical fact they did do. 

In the next place notice should be taken of Dr. Van Til’s account of Descartes. In the mimeographed syllabus on Christian Theistic Evidences, page 96, Dr. Van Til says that Descartes “studied the mind as an entity that had nothing to do with the body.”

But in The Principles of Philosophy, Part Two, Descartes states his second thesis as “How we likewise know that the human body is closely connected with the mind.” In Part Four of the same work, section 189, Descartes says, “We must know, therefore, that although the human soul is united to the whole body, it has, nevertheless, its principal seat in the brain...” And a few lines below: “the movements which are thus excited in the brain by the nerves variously affect the soul or mind, which is intimately conjoined with the brain...” Cf. passim. Again, as in the case of the scholastics, there seems to be a discrepancy between Dr. Van Til’s account and the sources. 

Dr. Van Til continues, in his Christian Theistic Evidences, to say, “Descartes thought of the mind in exclusively intellectual terms. ‘L’ame pense toujours’ was the principle of his psychology. The emotional and the volitive were disregarded.” But it should not be forgotten that Descartes wrote a volume On the Passions of the Soul. A brief indication that Descartes did not disregard the volitional and the emotional aspects of man’s nature is found in Article 18 of this work: “Our volitions are of two kinds...” And then Descartes goes on to distinguish them. Article 41 of the same work says, “The will is so free in its nature that it can never be constrained...” Article 45 says, “Our passions cannot be directly excited or removed by the action of the will; but they can be indirectly through the representation (or, imagination) of things which are customarily joined with the passions...” 

Nor is it necessary to confine the evidence to Descartes work On the Passions of the Soul. The Meditations themselves show that Dr. Van Til is not altogether accurate. In Meditation IV Descartes explains error on the ground of a certain relation between the understanding and the will: “I observe that these (errors) depend on the concurrence of the two causes, viz. the faculty of cognition which I possess, and that of election or the power of free choice -- in other words, the understanding and the will.” Then Descartes continues for a few pages to discuss the will, in spite of the fact that Dr. Van Til asserts that Descartes disregarded the volitional aspect of man’s personality. Further evidence will be found in Descartes’ Reply to the Second Objection.

Then Dr. Van Til continues: “The mind of man was thought of as being independent of God.” How could this assertion be made when two thirds the way through Meditation III Descartes writes: “I possess the perception (notion) of the infinite before that of the finite; that is, the perception of God before that of myself, for how could I know that I doubt, desire, or that something is wanting to me, and that I am not wholly perfect, if I possessed no idea of a being more perfect than myself, by comparison of which I knew the deficiencies of my nature?” 

A little further on Descartes writes: “I am desirous to inquire further whether I, who possess this idea of God, could exist supposing there were no God...” And then he goes on to argue at considerable length that first he could not be dependent on himself; second, that he could not be dependent on his parents; third, that there could not be several causes as the ultimate explanation of his being; and then for some pages Descartes stresses his dependence on God. Finally he says, “And in truth it is not to be wondered at that God at my creation implanted this idea (of God) in me, that it might serve, as it were, for the mark of the workman impressed on his work.” And then, “I not only find that I am an incomplete (imperfect), and dependent being,... but at the same time I am assured likewise that he upon whom I am dependent possesses in himself all the goods after which I aspire... and that he is thus God.” But Dr. Van Til asserts that Descartes thought of the mind of man as independent of God! 

Dr. Van Til’s book, The New Modernism, is also faulty in its understanding of philosophy. On page 11 he says, “Leibniz thought it was possible for man, by means of a refined logical apparatus, to learn to distinguish one penguin from another.” 

Now, Leibniz, in his Discourse on Metaphysics, VIII, (where he is talking about Alexander the Great instead of penguins) says “God, however, seeing the individual concept, or haecceity, of Alexander, sees there at the same time the basis and reason of all the predicates which can be truly uttered regarding him; for instance that he will conquer Darius... - facts which we can learn only through history.” Ibidem XIII:: “If anyone were capable of carrying out a complete demonstration by virtue of which he could prove this connection of the subject... with the predicate,… he would bring us to see” etc. Apparently therefore Leibniz teaches that man is not capable of distinguishing one person or one penguin from another by pure logic. Bearing on the same subject, even if not so directly, is ibidem V: “To know in particular, however, the reasons which have moved him (God) to choose this order of the universe... - this passes the capacity of a finite mind, above all when such a mind has not come into the joy of the vision of God.” This passage places limitations on human knowledge which Dr. Van Til apparently misses in Leibniz. 

Dr. Van Til continues on page 11 to say, “All knowledge, he contended, that is all true knowledge, is speculative or analytical at bottom. By working up the contents of your mind you may eventually learn all the fields of truth and all they contain.” 

Now, if the word analytical be omitted, the phrase all true knowledge (what would false knowledge be?) and the word, speculative, in Dr. Van Til’s sentence are sufficiently vague to make the sentence true in some sense or other. But Leibniz never taught that all knowledge was analytical. In the Discourse XIII, Leibniz teaches that some truths are not analytical, but contingent. Some predicates cannot be obtained from their subjects by the law of contradiction; and even in God’s perfect knowledge, the “demonstration” of the predicate is not as absolute as are those of numbers or geometry. The contrary does not imply a contradiction, and hence not all truth is analytic. Cf. further, On the Ultimate Constitution of Things, of Nov. 23, 1697.

In view of these items that have now been analyzed, it is necessary to conclude that there are historical inaccuracies in Dr. Van Til’s treatment of philosophy. Since the items analyzed are not matters of delicate interpretation where one man’s opinion is almost as good as another’s, but are matters of historical fact, the reader is cautioned not to accept Dr. Van Til’s every statement without examination. And if caution is required in the purely historical portion of his work, it would seem reasonable to use even more caution in the study of his constructive argumentation. What it is important to see is that the philosophic background of the Complaint is not to be accepted uncritically. In view of this philosophic background one has prima facie reason to suspect the epistemology and apologetics of the Complaint. It must be clear to anyone who has studied that document that its ideas and accusations are largely based on Dr. Van Til’s views, and hence the truth and the accuracy of the philosophic work behind the Complaint are of tremendous importance in estimating its value. Not that the Complaint should be condemned on mere suspicion: the suspicion will be verified by an examination of the document itself.  

THE COMPLAINT AND ITS PHILOSOPHY  

Of all the documents in the present controversy the Complaint is the most important. It is not the impromptu answers of a single person to a barrage of questions, but it is the result of extended collaboration. Any mistake that one person might have made on the spur of the moment had to pass the inspection of, and would be corrected by, all the other authors. Hence its wording must be considered the most accurate possible; and its presentation must be the most authoritative presentation of the views of those men. It was written, signed, and published by Professor R.B. Kuiper, Professor Paul Woolley, Professor Cornelius Van Til, Professor Edward J. Young—five members of the faculty of Westminster Theological Seminary, and also by Mr. Arthur W. Kuschke and Mr. Leslie W. Sloat, who were at that time connected with the Seminary. (Six other men, not so directly connected with the Seminary, also collaborated.) Hence the Complaint must be considered as the actual position of the large majority of the Westminster faculty. Note in particular that a Complaint against a Presbytery is always a serious matter. And this Complaint speaks of an unblushing humanistic rationalism and vicious independence of God. The awfulness of this charge, and the widespread publicity given to the document, all show that this must have been the most carefully prepared statement that these professors could make. It must accurately express their deepest convictions. Let us then examine this most important document. 

The Complaint admits that Dr. Clark distinguishes between what may be called the divine psychology and human psychology in the act of knowing. God’s mode of knowing is intuitive, while man’s is always temporal and discursive. This distinction, the Complaint claims, is insufficient; a further distinction is needed. It is obvious therefore that the complainants hold to a two-fold theory of something in addition to a two-fold theory of the act of knowing. 

Note too that the difference they wish to establish between God’s knowledge and man’s knowledge is not that God knows and man does not know all the implications of a given truth. This, of course, is true, but it is not the distinction the Complaint insists upon. The Complaint insists on a two-fold theory of something connected with a single truth itself, quite apart from its implications (cf. The Complaint, p.6, col. 2). 

A little examination will show that this other something, of which the complainants say they are two kinds - one for God and one for man, is the truth itself. The Complaint teaches a two-layer theory of truth. On page 5, col. 1, it says, “Dr. Clark denies that there is any qualitative difference between the contents of the knowledge of God and the contents of the knowledge possible to man.” Since they make this as an objection, it must be that they assert a qualitative difference between the contents of the knowledge of God and the contents of the knowledge possible to man.

At this point the important question arises, what are the contents of one’s knowledge Obviously the contents of one’s knowledge are the truths one knows. The only answer to the question, what does one know? is a list of the truths known. Truth is the object and content of knowledge. The contents of God’s knowledge are the truth he knows, and the contents of a man’s knowledge are the truth the man knows. The Complaint maintains that these two sets of truths are qualitatively different. 

This qualitative difference between the truths God knows and the truths that man knows is further emphasized in The Complaint, page 5, col. 2, bottom. Again as an unacceptable conclusion from Dr. Clark’s views they state, “a proposition would have to have the same meaning for man as for God.” Since this is unacceptable to them, the Complaint must teach that a proposition does not have the same meaning for man as for God. Propositions therefore have two meanings. ‘David was king of Israel’ means one thing for us; it means something different for God. What is means for God, we cannot know because the meaning God has is qualitatively different from ours, and man can never have God’s meanings. 

The culmination of this argument in the Complaint The culmination of this argument in the Complaint is reached in the next column: p.5, col. 3. To make sure that everyone would understand that this is the crux of the matter, to make everyone see that this is the distinction between God’s knowledge and man’s knowledge that the doctrine of incomprehensibility requires, the complainants have put it in italics. Here is found the main point of the whole discussion. The Complaint says, “we dare not maintain that his knowledge and our knowledge coincide at any single point” (italics theirs).

Note well that the complainants are not content to say that God’s knowledge differs from man’s in certain ways, such as in its extent and in its mode. They insist that there is no point of contact whatever. Not a single point. Far from denying that there is a single point of coincidence, I maintain that there is an area of coincidence. That area includes, “David was king of Israel,’ and ‘Jesus was born at Bethlehem,’ and several other items. These are the points where God’s knowledge and man’s knowledge coincide. The propositions mean to the man who knows them, to the man who grasps their meaning, exactly what they mean to God, although God, as was said knows implications of these propositions that man does not know; but the truth itself is the same for man as it is for God. If a man does not grasp God’s truth, he grasps no truth at all, for there is no other truth than God’s truth. God knows all truth. And if a man grasps any truth at all, since it is God’s truth, that truth is a point or even an area of coincidence. 

The Complaint, on the other hand, makes the truth God has qualitatively different from the ‘truth’ man has. There is not a single point in common. Whatever meaning God has, man cannot have. And since the Bible teaches that God has all truth, it must follow on the theory of the Complaint that man has no truth. The theory of the Complaint is therefore skepticism. 

Another passage in the Complaint serves to make the matter still more clear. A paragraph above has discussed the meaning of content. The Complaint itself specifies the sense in which it uses this term. On page 7 col. 3, it states another unacceptable conclusion in propositions these words: “This knowing of propositions cannot, in the nature of the case, reflect or inspire recognition by man of his relation to God, for the simple reason that the propositions have the same content, mean the same, to God and man.” Note that these last few words equate same content with mean the same, Thus it is clear that according to the Complaint the content is the meaning. And it follows that the Complaint holds that propositions do not mean the same thing for God as they do for men. There is no point of coincidence between the meaning a man has and the meaning God has. 

No one therefore can logically avoid the conclusion that the Complaint teaches a skeptical two-layer theory of truth. A proposition is its meaning. A proposition is not the sound waves in the air; a proposition is not the ink marks on paper; a proposition is not the words used. Mens semper cogitat; l’âme pense toujours; the mind always thinks: these are not three propositions—they are one and the same proposition, one and the same truth (or, falsehood), because they are identical in meaning. The Complaint holds that God has one set of meanings, and man has another set (if he have any at all). There is not a single point of coincidence.

The application of this skeptical theory to the practical matter of the preaching of the Gospel is also seen in the last quotation. The Complaint said, “This knowing of propositions cannot, in the nature of the case, reflect or inspire any recognition by man of his relation to God, for the simple reason that the propositions have the same content, mean the same, to God and man.”

The Complaint here teaches that if a man had the same meaning God had of a proposition, (such as, Christ died for sin), he could not for that very reason recognize his relation to God. Before a man can be inspired to recognize his relation to God, he must put on propositions a meaning different from God’s. Why is this? What use would the Bible be to us, if its words could not mean the same thing to us as they do to God? And what sort of a God is it that could not express, could not reveal, his meaning to man? Or, conversely, how could sentences that mean one thing to God and something else to man reflect or inspire any proper recognition by man of his relation to God? The import of the Complaint in this passage seems to render the preaching of the Gospel futile.

And therefore the Complaint, collaborated upon, signed, and published by a majority of the Westminster faculty, teaches a two-layer theory of truth. And its theory is not in accord with Reformed theology. It is a theory of skepticism that should be attacked and refuted, rather than defended and inculcated, by a faculty subscribing to the Westminster Confession.  

A SUBSEQUENT PAPER

Since the publication of the Complaint, some verbal claims have been made that the Complaint is not an accurate presentation of the views of its signers. It has been said that the complainants have changed their views and have moved closer to the Reformed faith. And a paper sent To the Commissioners to the Thirteenth General Assembly, by a Committee for the Complainants, is appealed to as evidence. This subsequent paper we must examine, although, in the absence of a retraction by the complainants themselves, such a mimeographed paper can be only of secondary importance. If the complaint no longer represents the position of the complainants, they should, I think, publicly repudiate it and apologize for its skeptical philosophy and baseless accusations. But since this subsequent paper, in its very first paragraph, condemns The Answer, one would imagine that it is consistent with The Complaint.

An examination of the first part of this paper, the section on The Incomprehensibility of God, will show this to be the case: the complainants have not changed their views. The paper expounds the same objectionable doctrine that is found in the Complaint. 

It is true that at one point the papers seems to withdraw from the position of the Complaint. On page 3 it says, “Truth is one. And man may and does know the same truth that is in the divine mind…” This statement is entirely acceptable because it flatly contradicts the Complaint. And if the paper as a whole consistently maintained this view, it too would be acceptable. But it is soon seen that this, which seems to be a retraction is but a temporary and superficial lapse from their fixed doctrines. The very same paragraph continues to say that man “cannot possibly have in mind a conception to eternity that is identical or that coincides with God’s own thought of his eternity.” This is nothing else than the doctrine of the Complaint over again. In the first lines of the paragraph they say that man can have the same truth that is in the divine mind, and immediately below they say that man cannot have the concept of eternity. The conception of eternity that the complainants have—not God’s conception of eternity—is the conception of endless years. If this is not God’s conception of eternity, it must follow that the complainants have the wrong conception of eternity. Man, according to them, cannot know that God is eternal; he can only know that God has endless duration. Endless duration is an analogy of eternity. God has the truth; man has only an analogy of the truth, and he can be quite sure that he does not have the truth itself.

The committee that wrote this paper attempts to support its contention by pointing out that the Bible frequently speaks of eternity in terms of endless years. The paragraph in question stresses God’s condescension or accommodation in revelation. This Scriptural language is well known; God is called the Ancient of Days; he is from everlasting to everlasting; and his years shall not fail. But to argue from these facts to the conclusion that man can have no other concept of eternity except that of endless duration is to argue badly. From the fact that revelation sometimes accommodates itself to man in figures of speech, it does not follow, as this papers says it does, that "therefore he cannot possibly have in mind a conception of eternity that is identical or that coincides with God’s own thought of his eternity.”

The Scriptures also speak of the arm of the Lord, the hand of God, and the eyes of God. Does it follow that we can have no other concept of the being of God expect the concept of a corporeal being? Hand and eyes are figures of speech, and we know that they are figures of speech because the Bible teaches that God is a pure Spirit. Similarly we know that ‘endless years’ is a figure of speech because in literal language the Bible teaches that God is immutable and eternal.

The conclusion this paper insists upon here is denied in the paragraph itself, for the authors betray the fact that they themselves have a concept of eternity different from that of endless duration. If they had no concept of eternity other than that of an everlasting lapse of time, how would they be able to say, “he is not subject to the passing of time. God’s being is without succession.” If they did not have the concept of “without succession,” they could not have discussed it in this paper. 

However, in spite of this testimony from their own material, the committee for the complainants denies that man’s concept and God’s coincide or are identical. It is true that this paragraph asserts a “correspondence” between God’s thought and man’s thought. But if man’s concept of “correspondence” is no more like God’s than man’s concept of eternity is said to be, how can one be sure that man means the same thing as God would mean if he says man thought corresponds to God’s? To be sure of a correspondence between two things, it is necessary that both of them be present to consciousness. No one can compare two things if he is acquainted with only one of them. Correspondences and analogies cannot be founded except on some point or area of coincidence. Obviously therefore the complainants have not been converted to the view that truth is one and that man may have it. They still hold that man has only an analogy of the truth and not the truth itself. 

On page 6 of the same paper their theory of truth is further elaborated. About the middle of the page we read, “The distinction between knowledge of a truth and knowledge of its implications is artificial and atomistic.” But if a premise is not distinguishable in meaning from a conclusion, then all truths have been merged into one homogeneous mass and reasoning has become impossible. Consider the distinction between the axioms and theorems of geometry. One of the axioms is that “all right angles are equal.” One of the implications or theorems is that “the interior angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles.” Is there only an artificial distinction between these two statements? Is it not rather a perfectly natural distinction? The two propositions are essentially, not artificially, different in meaning. And if we extend our view and say that all truths are parts of one system, then the proposition ‘Moses spoke to Pharaoh,’ could in a sense be called a premise for the proposition ‘David was king of Israel.’ Why should the distinction between two such propositions be called artificial? What sort of epistemology is it that makes the meaning of one sentence - even though related to every other in the system - only artificially different from the meaning of another? 

The authors of this Subsequent paper proceed consistently. At the bottom of this paragraph on page 6 they say, “the human mind likewise cannot know it as a bare proposition, apart from an actual understanding of implications.” 

While the context refers to one specific proposition, the theory requires this pronouncement to be applied to every proposition. The authors must hold that no proposition can be understood apart from an actual understanding of implications.

The first question that occurs is, why not? Their assertion that it is so, does not make it so. For example, take the proposition ‘some books are not interesting.’ This is a particular negative, and in the traditional Aristotelian logic a particular negative, while it may be expressed in several forms, does not by itself imply another proposition of different meaning. But if it has no implications, then according to the theory we cannot know what it means. But that is absurd. Have the complainants given sufficient thought to logic to justify their assertion? And quite aside from the technicalities of Aristotelian or non-aristotelian logic, one must ask this second question: when a child is for the first time taught that one plus one are two, does the child have an “actual understanding of implications?” According to this theory, before a child can understand the first propositions, he must understand a second proposition—its implications; and of course before he can understand this second proposition, he must understand a third—its implication; and before and so on. The child must know everything before he knows anything. This fits in exactly with the skeptical theory which the Complaint and this Subsequent paper defend. 

The authors of the paper may wish to reply that they did not mean to say that the child had to understand all the implications; they meant merely that he has to understand some of the implications. 

But look at the sentence again. The world “likewise” seems to indicate that they mean all the implications, for the word “likewise” refers to a comparison between God’s knowledge and man’s knowledge. Note that they say, “The divine mind cannot know that truth without knowing its implications and the human mind likewise cannot know it” etc. The force of the comparison seems to require man to have an actual understanding of all the implications. In other words, a man must be omniscient, if he is to know anything at all, for he cannot know any single truth without an actual understanding of (its) implications. 

Although this interpretation is required by their argument, they may have omitted the word ‘its’ purposely, not noticing that such a purposeful omission ruins their comparison of the divine mind with the human. Now, if they withdraw from their position and try to claim that a man must understand only a few implications before he can understand his first proposition, there is another question that the complainants must answer. They must explain how many implications are needed before a man knows the first proposition. Is it necessary to understand ten theorems of geometry before it is possible to understand an axiom? Or five theorems? Or just one? Then the complainants will have to explain what principle they use to limit the number of five rather than ten, or to one rather than two. When they attempt to make these explanations, it will be clear that they are in utter confusion. If anyone of us will look into his own mind and consider the truths he knows, he will find many propositions there without an actual understanding of their implications.

Before ending this part of the discussion, I wish to draw attention to the following assertions of the paper in question. On page 7, paragraph 1, are these words: “Dr. Clark’s fundamental insistence upon identity (italics theirs) of divine and human knowledge...” On page 8 near the bottom we find, “Dr. Clark insists upon identity of divine and human knowledge of a particular truth…”

It is amazing that these men continue to circulate these false statements after I have so many times denied them, I denied them in the examination (cf. Transcript, 31:9-10). I denied them in speeches in two Assemblies and in countless conversations. The Report of the committee to the thirteenth General Assembly denied them for me (page 3, next to the bottom paragraph). And in spite of all this, the committee for the complainants has neither seen nor heard these denials, and continue to make the same false statements. Truly, this is incomprehensible.

THE BIBLICAL DOCTRINE  

Now let us turn to Reformed doctrine; but instead of examining the Westminster Confession, we may better go directly to the source of authority and examine the Scriptures. It will be highly instructive to contrast the Scriptures with the skeptical theory of the Complaint. 

The Gospel of John, which so emphasizes the Godhood of Jesus Christ, has a great deal to say about truth.

John 1:17 Grace and truth came through Jesus Christ.

5:53 Ye have sent unto John, and he hath borne witness unto the truth.

8:32 And ye shall know the truth

Does anyone now dare to say that there is not even a single point of coincidence between God’s knowledge and ours? Is there in this, or in what follows, any hint of a two-layer theory of truth? Are there two qualitatively different truths? Do we possess only an analogy of the truth?

John 8:45 I say the truth.

15:7 I tell you the truth.

16:13 He shall guide you into all truth.

17:17 Sanctify them in thy truth; thy word is truth.

The Word is not something qualitatively different from the truth. The sentences in the Word do not properly bear a meaning different from the meaning God has. The Word is the truth, the truth of God, and we have that truth.

Cf. Also: I Kings 17:24, Psalms 25:5, 43:3, 86:11, 119:43, 142, 151; Rom. 1:18, 3:7; II Cor. 6:7, 7:14, 11:10; Gal. 2:5, 14; Eph. 1:13, Etc. 

These verses do not indicate that we cannot grasp God’s meaning or that the truth cannot be known, or that God cannot be known. 

Since God is truth, this whole matter involves the question of our knowledge of God. Can we know God? It will do us no good, if we can know only something qualitatively different from God; it will not help if there is no point of contact between us and God. The question is, can we know God? If answer be made in terms of negation and analogy alone; if all possibility of God’s knowledge and man’s coinciding at any point be denied; if no sentence in the bible can possibly have the same meaning for man that it has for God; the logical result is a skepticism that makes revelation impossible and Christianity a vain dream. But if man can know some things that God knows; if man can grasp some of God’s meaning; if God’s knowledge and man’s have some points in common; then true religion will be no delusion, but a glorious reality.

Gordon Clark: Unnamed Letter to Editor (The Southern Presbyterian Journal)

1950. Unnamed Letter to Editor. The Southern Presbyterian Journal Vol. IX, No. 20. Nov. 15.

Sir:

For several years I have subscribed to and have read The Southern Presbyterian Journal.  I think you are doing a great work and doing it very well. If I should make a criticism, it would be with constructive intent, for I am anxious that you may be able to save the Southern Presbyterian Church for the gospel, or at least bring into being a vigorous continuing Presbyterian church.

The opposed forces are alert to take advantage of any mistake the faithful may make and in order to reduce these, may I speak of your article in the issue of October 18, entitled "Poison In The Stream." I assure you that my criticism is made in all kindness and with a genuine desire toward the same ends you desire. But there is one specific point and one more general point, I would like to bring to your attention.

On page 8, column 2, you refer to a professor of logic who taught you that a false premise will inevitably lead to a false conclusion. If the professor indeed taught this, I am bold to say that he was incompetent in logic. A false premise may validly lead to a true conclusion. For example; All the heroes of Homer's Illiad died young (false); Alexander was a hero of the Illiad (false); therefore, (validly) it follows that Alexander died young. The accepted logical doctrine, accepted for two thousand years is that a false premise validly implies anything. Therefore, it can imply true as well as false conclusions. In modern symbolic logic this is expressed as "zero implies one."

There is a more general comment I would like to make — not with the same dispatch and emphasis, yet with a hope that it may be of help. I not only teach logic, but I teach the philosophy of religion. And I use books as poisonous as Enslin's. But the effect on students does not come so much from books as from the instructor in using them. I can use these books and show their prejudice, their lack of evidence and their fallacies. Someone else might produce a totally different effect. It seems to me therefore that you will never make much progress attacking colleges or seminaries on the ground that they use such books. The standard answer in such cases is too obviously true, viz., that the students need to know what is being said in the professorial world. I am distressed that I cannot indicate a better approach. My little wisdom is limited to the opinion that an attack on text books is the wrong approach. The basic factor is to insure the orthodoxy of the faculty and when this weakens I do not know how to go about correcting it. A new president is probably needed, or a new board of directors. And on such matters I am sure you are wiser than I.

Let me assure you again that I write in the spirit of co-operation; and if any phrases here appear harsh or summary, or in any way displease you, I must humbly apologize.

Gordon H. Clark,

Indianapolis, Ind.

Monday, December 26, 2022

Gordon Clark: Wheaton Resignation Notes

The following are notes by Clark concerning his resignation from Wheaton. One can read the original scans here

I have not transcribed several letters that have already been published in Clark and His Correspondents (link), which can be bought as a searchable ebook. My goal in transcribing any of Clark's thought has been to make searchable what is not already [easily] searchable. One exception to this is the two paragraphs below which begin with "Or else?" and "Now for ordination." These paragraphs were clearly meant to be cut in the letter Clark sent to Bob, but as they are in the public domain and not included in Clark and His Correspondents, I have transcribed them, as they give a fuller understanding of what was going through Clark's mind during this time he describes as a "theology of crisis" he thought would (and, in fact, did) affect "the rest of [his] life" (see below).

Each distinctive note is separated by "------." As with my last transcription, if I take a more or less educated guess as to what I think Clark meant, I put "[?]" after the word. Clark misspells some words; I've left those misspellings unedited. He has also had certain points in his writing during which he either struck out a thought or drawn lines or made asterisks to update his flow of thought or writing. I have tried to make these points intelligible below, but if anyone is confused by this, he or she can read the original scans to compare with my attempt.

1942. Wheaton Resignation Notes.

On the evening of June 30 1942 a committee of the trustees of Wheaton College, composed of Doctors Edman, McCarrell, Fuller, Ironside, and Mr. Fischer, met with me. They had heard complaints from certain members of the faculty, from students, and from the parents of students respecting my theological views.

The session lasted from 7:30 P.M. to 10:30 P.M., and most of the time was taken up by their attempt to learn my views and my attempt to explain them. I was handicapped by what appeared to be the almost complete ignorance of the historic position of the reformed churches. For example, Dr. Fuller was abruptly taken aback when told him that the Westminster Confession taught the doctinre of reprobation.

Although argued that position carefully set down by learned men and accepted by a score of denominations for three hundred years could not legitimately be called extreme, I am confident that they all regard reprobation and the foreordination of sinful acts of men as incredibly extreme.

Some time was given to the consideration of the statements of students who had learned of Calvinism. I gather that they think I am responsible not only for every absurd statement one of my students makes, but that I am also responsible for great many absurdities committed by students with whom have never talked.

When I raised the matter of the secret method of dropping the philosophy major and the false statements circulated about me and certain of my friends who are outside the college, Mr. Fischer informed me that the committee had not come to discuss personal discourtesy.

The committee took no action, nor did it make any suggestions. Mr. Fischer personally suggested more cautious expression of views.

I do not know whether the committee plans to meet again or not. One of the members, I think it was Mr. Fischer, intimated that if the situation did not improve, the trustees would be forced to do something or other.

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

Dec. 15 1942 Dr. Edman for[?] the first[?] reported that the Board had not acted on the Committees report at their meeting in October.

Dr. E. told me on Dec. 31. Report accepted and services terminated, at meeting a few days before

Jan 21, Fischer said he would ask trustees to rescind motion[?] and let me resign.

Track team ran on Sunday Nov 23 1942

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

Mrs. Anderson also wrote to Schoon[?] on Sept 27 1941. Schoon[?] answered on Dec. 18 1941, and signed himself assistant[?] to the Dean of Men. Yet the Dean’s office kept Wm. [?] A. in our house the year of 41 and 42 and would have let him return for 42 and 43, had we not discovered Mrs. Anderson’s protest and insisted that he live elsewhere.

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

To take effect at the close of the present semester I hereby present my resignation as Asso Prof of Phil. at Wheaton College in protest against two phases of current policy.

First: the philosophy major was dropped from the catalog without departmental recommendation, without committee action, without or faculty approval. One cannot submit to such an underhanded procedure and retain self respect. I am also at variance with the policy of lowering such[?] graduation and entrance requirements, and the general lack of encouragement, to original productive work by the not to mention the positive handicaps, with reference to scholarly productivity by the faculty.

Second: while the college has the undisputed right to require a sincere adherence to the doctrinal position stated in the catalog, I have been denied the right to acquaint the students [an attempt is being made to deny students the right to be acquainted], either in class or in a student club, with the historic position of the several Presbyterian Churches denominations, the several Reformed Churches, the Congregational bodies, a large number of Baptist churches – in general the position of the greatest Reformers men of the Protestant reformation.* Cooperation [with the Trustees] is [being] defined as compliance with the theology of one or a few individuals, a theology never adopted by any denomination, nor by Wheaton College. The unauthorized imposition of new standards, contrary to the historic creeds of Protestantism, is on a par with the unauthorized dropping of the philosophy major, and its cause.

I am entirely out of sympathy with this situation and, to maintain my self respect and to permit Wheaton College to function ad the Trustees (?) desire, I must resign my position as _________

*Keeping the students thus in ignorance is neither intellectually worthy of a college nor morally worthy of a Christian.

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

Or else? Find a church. That requires ordination. I am the world’s worst diplomat, but maybe I could keep a church going. I even think that without too much bad luck I could convince an independent group to enter the OPC. Of course the group would have to be found first. It might have to be founded, and that would be a harder job. Whether I would be more useful in a church or in teaching is another consideration. 

For any light you have on the situation I shall thank you. I feel job now like the theology of crisis. That is, my present decision (if it is I and not the Trustees who decide) will probably stand for, quite lkely, the rest of my life. If a change is to be made, now is the time, and I want all the wisdom I can gather.

...

Now for ordination. As I think I said in my last letter, Marsden raised the question about two years ago. I said No, rather positively, because I thought I was fixed for life, and as a professor I did not need it. But the idea remained, and I broached it to Woolley about a year ago. Then I postponed it because I wanted to serve on the Committee of Nine. The only deterring consideration now is the particular mess in which I find myself. That the situation has a bearing on my desire for ordination, I do not deny; certainly it has accelerated the progress of thought. And now that it is time to settle some problems, other problems also might as well be settled also.

Will you therefore kindly join with Woolley (if he will) and present the enclosed paper to the Philadelphia Presbytery?

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

May 9 1942

Dear Paul,

In view of our friendship for the past ten years, and to conclude a matter that has been revolving in my mind for a little while, would you be so kind as to join with Bob Strong in presenting the enclosed (self-explanatory) paper to the Philadelphia Presbytery?

I should be greatly obliged if you can consent to do this for me.

It the Presbytery cares to consider that matter, perhaps a meeting in the summer could be arranged. It would be most convenient, if perchance the Committee of Nine is continued and if I am still on it, to have these two meetings on successive days. But such details will take care of themselves.

Cordially yours,

Gordon

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

May 19 1942

Mr. Allan C. Emery

King Oak Hill

Weymouth Heights, Mass.

My dear Mr. Emery,

Your son, whom we enjoyed having with us during his year at Wheaton, told me to be free to write to him or to you, if occasion should arise. There is an occasion now.

But since I have not heard from Allan for some time, I fear that he might be in the armed forces. Therefore I have written to him but am enclosing the letter with this to you. If he is home, I judge that both of you will read it.

Very truly yours,

----------------------------------------------------------------------------

May 19 1942

Mr. Allan C. Emery

King Oak Hill

Weymouth Heights, Mass.

Dear Allan,

On one or two occasions you told me that if I had any matter concerning the college which I desired to present to your father as trustee, I should feel free to write to you or to him. In the present situation I think it to proper to write; it is the first time, and it may be the last.

First an account of the situation must be made. Owing to the war and to the budget it seems that some, retrenchments in the college must be made. This possibly affects the offering of some "majors” in the curriculum. When the material for the present catalog was being prepared, Dr. Thiessen told me that Dr. Edman wanted to see me about the philosophy major. I met Dr. Edman in the hall and he asked me to write a letter giving my views as to keeping or dropping it. With one of the young faculty men called into the army, I was asked to teach four hours of Greek. In my letter I showed how a philosophy major could be retained even while taught some Greek.

The next thing I knew the catalog was published with the philosophy major missing. There had been no departmental recommendation, no committee meeting, no faculty action. It seems to me that all matters pertaining to the curriculum should pass through the faculty. Therefore I asked in the faculty meeting if this were not the case, and how it was that the philosophy major was dropped without regular action. The faculty seemed to approve of my views and instructed the administration committee (composed largely of the heads of the departments) to discuss the matter and bring back a recommendation.

In this committee meeting it became clear that the war and the budget had virtually nothing to do with the matter, for I had some eighteen or twenty major students while other majors had less than five.

The real reason came to light in several accusations made against me. First, I was a Calvinist, and Wheaton ought not to be known as a Calvinistic school. Second, my students asked Dr. Thiessen embarrassing questions. Third, I gave my moral support to the Creed Club, a “disruptive" group of students that meet to study the Bible as interpreted by the reformed creeds.

I tried to reply to these accusations. First, I am a Calvinist. It is the doctrine of a dozen or more of the finest evangelical denominations. Wheaton is ostensibly an interdenominational school, and if Calvinism is persistently attacked (as it is), it ought to have also sympathetic presentation. Since do not have much time to discuss it in class (for the subject matter overlaps only at intervals), I am happy that the students meet in the Creed Club to study the matter. I cannot attend very often, but I certainly lend them my moral support.

The second charge was that my students ask Dr. Thiessen embarrassing questions. If this means that I suggest that they go and ask him questions, the charge is false. His students also come to me and ask questions. When they do so, I am neither embarrassed, nor do I think he has sent them to me. As a matter of fact, the students who know me best and sense the situation ask Dr. Thiessen very few questions. Most of the questions come from students who are simply seeking information, and yet the students tell me that Dr. Thiessen takes nearly every question as personal affront. In one case, if the students report correctly, a girl whom I do not know, who never has taken any work from me, asked a question, and Dr. Thiessen scolded her till she cried in class.

The third charge is of course along the same general line. The Creed Club asked to use a room in the New Dorm this year. They were granted permission. They conduct sober, dignified church service, with hymns, prayer, and what is practically a sermon. The Dean, however, charged that Calvinism was sect and tried to put them out. They asked to have the opportunity to speak before the Committee on Student Affairs. I think that they were not granted permission, but no furhter attempt was made to put them out. Far from being disruptive influence, they stand good deal of petty persecution. Calvinism is misrepresented, I can say even slandered in classes, and often students take the cue and openly snear at the members of the Creed Club.

Finally, in the meeting of the committee on administration, in which these charges had been made against me, Dr. Thiessen demanded that there be no mention of a theological position different from his made in the classes. And in particular, since I am in his department, I must never disagree with him. Of course I am free to believe as I please, but the students must never know it.

This demand is, I take it, a demand for my resignation. It comes at a very awkward time of the year, when it is difficult to find another position; and I am unwilling to resign without acquainting some of the trustees with the reasons. If the trustees wish to enforce the views of Dr. Thiessen and some of the others, that will settle the matter. But I must remind them that Calvinism has been a noble and dominant part of Protestantism, whereas Dr. Thiessen’s theology has never been adopted by any denomination and is only his personal production.

These are the facts as I see them, and I am writing this letter simply for your information.

Very sincerely yours,