Recently, I was reading
Gordon Lewis' summary and critique of Gordon Clark's apologetic in Testing
Christianity's Truth Claims. Clark said Lewis' representation of his
position here was done "better than any other critic" (Clark and
His Critics, 2009, pg. 394). Clark provides his own response to Lewis in
that book. I just want to highlight a few points related to Clark's apologetic
I think should be made clearer.
To begin his final
section of his chapter on Clark - his "Evaluation" - Lewis writes:
"Suppose for the moment that consistency is the sole test of truth-claims,
as Clark asserts." (Testing Christianity's Truth Claims, 1976, pg.
119). Clark points out this isn't true. In one of his earliest books
(originally published in the late 1940s), for example, Clark wrote: "While
consistency is one of the basic reasons for adopting a world-view, from a more
proximate standpoint the world-view must function as a practical
postulate" (A Christian Philosophy of Education, 1988, pg. 42). For
some reason, this tends to be an overlooked point.
For Christians,
apologetics serves a certain function: "to defend the truth of
Christianity against the attacks of its enemies" (link). Attacks can come in different varieties
and relate to different fields, but basically, they all question that
Christianity is true or knowable. If an apologetic has nothing to say about
these different fields and has no relevance to whether Christianity is true or
knowable, it isn't practical.
The other point I want
to make also relates to the function of apologetics. Lewis seems to make the
mistake of equating Clark's "test[s] for truth" with how a Christian
knows the truth. He mistakes Clark's apologetic for Clark's epistemology. Lewis
writes:
Admittedly, Christianity's truth-claims cannot be proved by inductive evidence. But Clark chooses to believe their truth because Christianity, of all the systems men have known, is alone consistent. Notice what is necessary for Clark to establish that thesis. He must show the inconsistency of every other system in history and on the contemporary scene... On what grounds does Clark know that there could not be two or more consistent systems? He assumes that only one system could possibly be consistent. (Testing Christianity's Truth Claims, 1976, pg. 119, 120)
Note that the following
isn't true: "Clark chooses to believe their truth because Christianity...
is alone consistent." Rather, Clark chooses to argue their
truth because Christianity is alone consistent. This is the difference between
apologetics and epistemology. Apologetics consists in making
arguments. This is not always so in epistemology - axioms are not known
because they are the conclusion of some argument, they are known because they
are self-authenticating.
Clark has to argue for
Christianity via logical consistency and practicality because, at the risk of
stating the obvious, he can't know Christianity for those to whom he is
engaging in apologetics. He could just say divine revelation is
self-authenticating and leave it at that, but it is more persuasive (which is
another function of apologetics) to additionally point out, when applicable,
that an opponent's system 1) can't be self-authenticating if his system
inconsistent or impractical, or 2) that his system is less coherent than
Christianity is, in the case of something like Judaism.
Lewis seems to think
that Clark's tests for truth are the basis on which Clark
claims to know Christianity. That is really the only explanation for why Lewis
would think Clark would have to sift through infinitely many systems before
knowing that just one, Christianity, is consistent. But that interpretation
goes completely against what Lewis himself stated Clark believed regarding the
nature and knowability of axioms earlier in his summary.
While "test[s] for
truth" can serve as confirmatory evidences of Christianity, they shouldn't
function as the ground of knowledge; divine revelation does. Elsewhere, I have
called tests for truth necessary conditions for knowledge and the postulate[s]
by which one claims to know anything the sufficient condition[s] for knowledge
(link). The former are the means by which we make
arguments for (i.e. apologetics) the latter (i.e. epistemology).
Again, apologetics
should include an explanation of the epistemology of the system one is
defending. Any good defense of a system of knowledge should explain what that
system says about how we can know anything. But that explanation and defense
should not be confused for that actual process of knowing. In fact, apologetics
is only possible insofar as we know the system we are defending is true in the
first place (see here).
As for where Clark
stated these points - that axioms are known because they are self-authenticating,
not the conclusion of an apologetic, and that consistency isn't the [sole]
means by which we know Christianity is true - a few quotes should suffice:
This disjunct faces two replies. First, it assumes that a first principle cannot be self-authenticating. Yet every first principle must be. The first principle of Logical Positivism is that a sentence has no meaning unless it can be verified (in principle at least) by sensory experience. Yet no sensory experience can ever verify this principle. Anyone who wishes to adopt it must regard it as self-authenticating. So it is with all first principles. (Christian Philosophy, 2004, pg. 47)
Undoubtedly I hold that truth is a consistent system of propositions. Most people would be willing to admit that two truths cannot be contradictories; and I would like to add that the complex of all truths cannot be a mere aggregate of unrelated assertions. Since God is rational, I do not see how any item of his knowledge can be unrelated to the rest. Weaver makes no comment on this fundamental characteristic of divine truth.
Rather, he questions whether this characteristic is of practical value, and whether it must be supplemented in some way. It is most strange that Weaver here says, “I must agree with Carnell,” as if he had convicted me of disagreeing with Carnell by providing no supplementation whatever. Now, I may disagree with the last named gentleman on many points, but since it is abundantly clear that I “supplement” consistency by an appeal to the Scripture for the determination of particular truths, it is most strange that Weaver ignores my supplementation. (Clark and His Critics, 2009, pg. 290)
I have sometimes entertained the notion that one of the chief differences between Clark's approach to apologetics and Van Til's approach to apologetics stems from their different contexts--Clark was a professor of philosophy at a university for a good portion of his career whereas Van Til was a seminary professor. That Van Til would choose to assert the "impossibility of the contrary" (to use Bahnsen's term) at the front end of an apologetic, prior to demonstrating the inconsistency or incoherence of the opponent's view makes better sense when instructing pastors and theologians. Clark's asserting the axiom of Christianity only after he has performed the destructive task makes better sense when training or responding to philosophers who are not pastors or theologians.
ReplyDeleteThat Clark hammered consistency and coherence as apologetic standards and not epistemological ones is probably one of the biggest mistakes that critics (and followers!) of Clark make, but hopefully less so with expositions such as yours here available.
Somewhat hilariously, their differences are similar to those of Barth and Brunner, though reversed.
ReplyDeleteBrunner was always a pastoral figure and thus accepted the notion of a point of contact for evangelistic and pastoral counseling purposes. Barth primarily a professor of theology and thus said "Nein" to any such notion and started with an impossibility of the contrary.
Ones contact with actual non-Christian people and experiences sharing the gospel with them seems to make a difference in apologetic approach, imo.
I've been reading Van Til's A Survey of Christian Epistemology recently. It's well written and engaging, which somewhat surprises me for as much as I've heard Van Til is difficult reading.
ReplyDeleteEither way, I see why he would argue the impossibility to the contrary, given his belief that truth is internally related. I can also see why this, coupled with his belief in divine simplicity, would lead to a theory of analogical knowledge. I plan to write a post on it soon, as it confirms a suspicion I had a few years ago.
What Josh said makes sense to me because I have noticed in the short time that I have looked at Van Til's approach (primarily through Bahnsen), it seems that Bahnsen has a better grasp on Philosophy than Van Til did and filled in some of the gaps that Van Til had.
ReplyDeleteReminds me of Gordon Clark and someone I know..........